ω and ω May Be the Only Minimal Uncountable Linear...

21
Michigan Math. J. 55 (2007) ω 1 and ω 1 May Be the Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders Justin Tatch Moore For Stephanie 1. Introduction In 1971 Laver proved the following result, confirming a long-standing conjecture of Fraïssé. Theorem 1.1 [10]. If L i (i < ω) is a sequence of σ -scattered linear orders, then there exist i<j such that L i is embeddable into L j . In particular, the σ -scattered orders are well-founded when given the quasi-order of embeddability. Here a linear order is scattered if it does not contain a copy of the rationals; a lin- ear order is σ -scattered if it is a countable union of scattered suborders. Around the same time, Baumgartner proved the following theorem. (As usual, ZFC is used to denote “Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice” and MA to denote “Martin’s axiom”.) Theorem 1.2 [3]. It is relatively consistent with ZFC—and follows from the proper forcing axiom (PFA)—that any two 1 -dense sets of reals are order- isomorphic. (A linear order is 1 -dense if every proper interval contains 1 ele- ments.) In particular, PFA implies that any subset of R of cardinality 1 is minimal with respect to not being σ -scattered. It is therefore consistent that Laver’s theorem is not sharp. However, it is unclear whether ZFC alone implies that there is a linear order that is minimal with respect to not being σ -scattered. Question 1.3. Is there a linear order that is not σ -scattered and that is minimal in this regard? Two important classes of linear orders that are not σ -scattered are the real types and the Aronszajn types: the real types are those uncountable dense linear orders that are separable; the Aronszajn types are those linear orders that are uncountable and yet have no uncountable suborders that are scattered or real types. This latter class was considered—and proved nonempty—long ago by Aronszajn and Kurepa in the context of Souslin’s problem. (The existence of Aronszajn lines was later Received July 27, 2006. Revision receivedApril 9, 2007. The research presented in this paper was funded by NSF grants DMS-0401893 and DMS-0200671. 437

Transcript of ω and ω May Be the Only Minimal Uncountable Linear...

Michigan Math. J. 55 (2007)

ω1 and −ω1 May Be the Only MinimalUncountable Linear Orders

Justin Tatch Moore

For Stephanie

1. Introduction

In 1971 Laver proved the following result, confirming a long-standing conjectureof Fraïssé.

Theorem 1.1 [10]. If Li (i < ω) is a sequence of σ-scattered linear orders, thenthere exist i < j such that Li is embeddable into Lj . In particular, the σ-scatteredorders are well-founded when given the quasi-order of embeddability.

Here a linear order is scattered if it does not contain a copy of the rationals; a lin-ear order is σ-scattered if it is a countable union of scattered suborders.

Around the same time, Baumgartner proved the following theorem. (As usual,ZFC is used to denote “Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice”and MA to denote “Martin’s axiom”.)

Theorem 1.2 [3]. It is relatively consistent with ZFC—and follows from theproper forcing axiom (PFA)—that any two ℵ1-dense sets of reals are order-isomorphic. (A linear order is ℵ1-dense if every proper interval contains ℵ1 ele-ments.) In particular, PFA implies that any subset of R of cardinalityℵ1 is minimalwith respect to not being σ-scattered.

It is therefore consistent that Laver’s theorem is not sharp. However, it is unclearwhether ZFC alone implies that there is a linear order that is minimal with respectto not being σ-scattered.

Question 1.3. Is there a linear order that is not σ-scattered and that is minimalin this regard?

Two important classes of linear orders that are not σ-scattered are the real typesand the Aronszajn types: the real types are those uncountable dense linear ordersthat are separable; the Aronszajn types are those linear orders that are uncountableand yet have no uncountable suborders that are scattered or real types. This latterclass was considered—and proved nonempty—long ago by Aronszajn and Kurepain the context of Souslin’s problem. (The existence of Aronszajn lines was later

Received July 27, 2006. Revision received April 9, 2007.The research presented in this paper was funded by NSF grants DMS-0401893 and DMS-0200671.

437

438 Justin Tatch Moore

rediscovered by Specker and thus they are sometimes referred to as Specker typesin the literature; see [18, 5.15] for a historical discussion of this point.) Bothof these classes have the property that they are closed under taking uncountablesuborders. Hence a model of set theory in which Question 1.3 has a negative an-swer cannot contain minimal real or Aronszajn types. This motivates the followingquestion.

Question 1.4. Is there a ZFC example of a minimal uncountable linear orderother than ω1 or −ω1?

Here −ω1 (often denoted ω∗1 in the literature) signifies the reverse of ω1. By thefollowing classical result of Sierpinski, the continuum hypothesis (CH) impliesthat there are no minimal real types.

Theorem 1.5 [16]. If X ⊆ R and |X| = |R|, then there is a Y ⊆ X with |Y | =|R| such that, if f ⊆ Y 2 is a monotonic function, then f differs from the identityon a set whose cardinality is less than |R|.The picture was less clear for Aronszajn lines. An important class of Aronszajnlines considered by Countryman and proved nonempty by Shelah [14] consists ofthe Countryman lines: uncountable linear orders C such that the coordinatewisepartial order on C2 is the union of countably many nondecreasing relations. Thefollowing theorem shows that, under a fairly mild set-theoretic assumption, suchlinear orders are minimal. (It is not entirely clear when this was first known orwho discovered the proof; a weaker statement was conjectured in [14] and repeatedagain in [4], and a proof can be obtained using techniques in [20].)

Theorem 1.6. MA(ℵ1) implies that every Countryman line is minimal.

In fact, this argument can be adapted to show that if a pair of Countryman linesare ℵ1-dense then they are either isomorphic or reverse-isomorphic.

It is natural to suspect that there should be an analog of Sierpinski’s result forAronszajn lines—that CH (or a stronger enumeration principle such as♦) impliesthat there are no minimal Aronszajn lines. In a somewhat surprising twist, how-ever, Baumgartner proved the following result, which rules out the conventionalmethod for proving that Question 1.3 is independent.

Theorem 1.7 [4]. ♦+ implies that there is a minimal Aronszajn line.

Baumgartner also noted that his construction in Theorem 1.7 produces a Souslinline and asked whether this is necessarily the case.

In this paper I will prove that the answer to Question 1.4 is negative. This canbe viewed as a companion to the following result.

Theorem 1.8 [12]. PFA implies that the class of uncountable linear orders hasa five-element basis consisting of X, ω1,−ω1, C, and −C, where X is an arbitraryset of reals of cardinality ℵ1 and C is a Countryman line.

The Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders 439

The members of this basis are each minimal and canonical (assuming PFA). Themain result of this paper shows that some hypothesis is needed to draw this con-clusion in all but the trivial cases.

The main ingredient in the proof is a variation on the notion of uniformizing aladder system coloring. A ladder system coloring is a sequence 〈fα : α ∈ lim(ω1)〉such that, for each α ∈ lim(ω1), the domain of fα is a ladder Cα on α and the rangeof fα is contained in ω. Here a ladder on a countable limit ordinal α is a cofinalsubset of α that has ordertype ω.

Whether all ladder system colorings can be uniformized—when there is aϕ : ω1 → ω such that fα =∗ ϕ � Cα for all relevant α—turns out to be of in-terest both in pure combinatorial set theory and in applications. (The notation =∗will be explained shortly.) For instance, a variation on this theme played a crucialrole in the solution of Whitehead’s problem (see [13]).

Devlin and Shelah [6] have shown that the assertion

(U) all ladder system colorings can be uniformized

implies 2ℵ0 = 2ℵ1. This is rather remarkable because, for any given ladder systemcoloring, there is a proper forcing that uniformizes it yet does not introduce realnumbers. The obstruction to obtaining the consistency of (U) with CH is thereforein the inability to iterate these forcings without introducing reals.

In this paper we will consider a weaker variant (A) of (U) that is consistentwith CH:

(A) every ladder system coloring can be T -uniformized for everyAronszajn tree T

(see Section 2). This variant is of interest because, in the presence of a mini-mal Aronszajn line, it implies that 2ℵ0 = 2ℵ1. Hence the conjunction of (A) andCH implies that there are no minimal Aronszajn lines and so, by Sierpinski’s re-sult (Theorem 1.5), there are no minimal uncountable linear orders other than ω1

and −ω1.

The main results of this paper are as follows.

Theorem 1.9. There is a proper forcing extension in which the continuum hy-pothesis and (A) are both true.

Theorem1.10. If (A) is true and there is a minimalAronszajn line, then 2ℵ0 = 2ℵ1.

Theorem 1.11. It is consistent that ω1 and −ω1 are the only minimal uncount-able linear orders.

It is worth noting at this point that, although the major technical difficulty of thispaper is in proving Theorem 1.9, the key idea for proving the main result was therealization that Theorem 1.10 is true. A more direct approach to Theorem 1.11would be to introduce, for a given Aronszajn line L, a suborder X of L into whichL cannot embed and then argue that this procedure can be iterated while preserv-ing that L does not embed into X. In fact, though hindsight will suggest that suchpreservation may be possible, it still seems to be a daunting task. This is especially

440 Justin Tatch Moore

true if one wishes to obtain models satisfying Theorem 1.11 together with otherhypotheses (see the discussion in Section 6). Theorem 1.10 allows us to take a lessdirect approach by linking the introduction of embeddings to the introduction ofreal numbers, a phenomenon that has already been extensively studied and has arelatively well-developed theory (see [15]).

In fact, the discovery of the proof is a direct consequence of studying the possi-bility of maximizing �2-sentences for H(ℵ+1 ) in the presence of CH. An examplerelated to my original motivations is discussed in Section 6. I would like to thankAli Enayat for bringing Question 1.4 to my attention at just the right time. I havealso taken this paper as an opportunity to present a framework for showing that aniteration of proper forcings does not introduce reals, which I feel makes the tasksat hand more transparent. This is the content of Section 4.

Some attempt has been made to keep this paper fairly self-contained—providedthe reader is fluent in modern set-theoretic techniques. The reader is assumed tohave some knowledge of proper forcing in addition to the usual proficiency in settheory. For the most part I will follow the notation in [9], to which the reader is re-ferred for background in basic set theory and forcing. I will use the language fromcategory theory in parts of the paper; [11] will be used as the standard reference.Further information on iterated proper forcing can be found in [15]. All ordinalsconsidered in this paper are von Neumann ordinals: they are the set of their pre-decessors. In particular, ω is the set of all finite ordinals and ω1 is the set of allcountable ordinals. If two functions f and g have a common domain D and if{x ∈D : f(x) �= g(x)} is finite, then I will write f =∗ g; if f is constantly i ex-cept on a finite set, then I will write f ≡∗ i. Throughout the paper, θ will alwaysrefer to an uncountable regular cardinal. For a given θ, H(θ) will denote the col-lection of all sets of hereditary cardinality less than θ; hence H(ℵ+1 ) consists ofall sets of hereditary cardinality at most ℵ1. (The reader may be puzzled by theuse of ℵ+1 instead of ℵ2: the point is that H(ℵ+1 ) is more suggestive of the typicalcardinality of its members.) These structures are of interest since, for a given θ,H(θ) satisfies all of the axioms of ZFC except the power set axiom and is closedunder taking subsets. Such structures will always be tacitly equipped with a fixedwell-ordering that is used to generate Skolem functions for the structure.

One major departure from the norm will be the emphasis on countable transi-tive set models. It will be convenient to utilize the following specialized notation.If M is a set, then there is a unique transitive set M and a unique collapsing iso-morphism from (M, ∈) to (M, ∈). (A set M is transitive if every element of M isalso a subset of M.) If an object is first named as M, then M will denote its tran-sitive collapse. Furthermore, if X is an element of M, then XM will denote theresult of applying M’s collapsing isomorphism to X. If ε is a function and X is asubset of the domain of ε, then εX will denote the image of X under ε.

2. Background on Trees

In this section I will present some background on trees and fix some notation. Thereader who is familiar with trees may wish to skip this section and refer to it if any

The Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders 441

of the notation is unfamiliar. Further reading as well as some historical discussioncan be found in [18].

Recall that a tree is a partial ordering (T, <) in which every set of the form {s ∈T : s < t} for t in T is well-ordered by < . The ordertype of this set is called theheight of t. All trees considered in this paper are, moreover, Hausdorff : if t �= t ′and if both have limit height then each has a different set of predecessors.

The set of all elements of T of a given height δ is denoted Tδ and is called theδth level of T. This allows us to make the following definitions.

Definition 2.1. If t is in T and if α is an ordinal, then t � α is t if α is at least theheight of t; otherwise, t � α is the element s of T such that s < t and the heightof s is α.

Definition 2.2. If s and t are incomparable elements of T, then �(s, t) is thegreatest ordinal ζ such that s � ζ = t � ζ.

We can also use restriction to define an abstract notion of a lexicographical order-ing on a tree.

Definition 2.3. If (T, <) is a tree, then a linear ordering ≤ lex on T is a lexico-graphical ordering if, whenever s and t are incomparable elements of T, s ≤lex t

is equivalent to s � (ζ + 1) ≤lex t � (ζ + 1), where ζ = �(s, t).

Our interest in trees will be limited to Aronszajn trees—those that are uncountablebut have countable levels and branches.

Theorem 2.4 (see [18, 5.1]). Every Aronszajn line is embeddable into a lexico-graphical ordering on an Aronszajn tree.

I will also need the notion of a subtree of an Aronszajn tree. (There is no universaldefinition of the term “subtree”; the following is the most appropriate definitionfor the discussion in this paper.)

Definition 2.5. A subtree of T is an uncountable subset U of T that is down-wards closed: if u is in U and t ≤ u, then t is in U. If every element of U hasuncountably many extensions in U, then U is said to be pruned.

Remark 2.6. If T is an Aronszajn tree and U is a subtree of T, then it is wellknown and readily verified that the set U ′ of all u in U that have uncountably manyextensions in U is a pruned subtree of U. In particular, every subtree of an Arons-zajn tree contains a pruned subtree.

Now we can formulate the statement (A) introduced in Section 1. Let T be anAronszajn tree and let �f = 〈fα : α ∈ lim(ω1)〉 be a ladder system coloring.

Definition 2.7. The coloring �f can be T -uniformized if there is a subtree U ofT and a function ϕ : U → ω such that, if u is an element of U of limit height α,then fδ =∗ ϕ[u] � Cα. Here ϕ[u] : α → ω is defined by ξ �→ ϕ(u � ξ).

442 Justin Tatch Moore

The statement (A) is then the assertion that every ladder system coloring can beT -uniformized for every Aronszajn tree T. Observe that this is a weaker statementthan (U); it becomes equivalent if we require that the upper bound on the error inϕ[u] depend only on the height of u.

I will finish this section with a lemma relating the minimality of Aronszajn linesto a more combinatorial notion of minimality that will be easier to work with. Re-call the following definition.

Definition 2.8. If S and T are two Aronszajn trees, then S is said to be club-embeddable into T if there is a closed unbounded set E ⊆ ω1 and an order-preserving function from S � E into T � E. Here S � E = ⋃

δ∈E Sδ.

Lemma 2.9. Suppose that T is an Aronszajn tree and that X ⊆ T is dense in thetree order that is a minimal Aronszajn line in some lexicographical order on T. (Asubset X of T is dense in T if every element of T has an extension in X.) If S isa subtree of

T ′ = {t ∈ T : ∃t0, t1 ∈ T(t ≤ t0, t1) and (t0 ⊥ t1)},then T ′ club-embeds into S. In particular, if there is a minimal Aronszajn line,then there is an Aronszajn tree that club-embeds into all of its subtrees.

I could not find this mentioned specifically in the literature, although a related dis-cussion can be found in [4]. I will leave the proof to the interested reader.

3. Coding Using (A) and a Minimal Aronszajn Line

In this section I will prove Theorem 1.10. I will need the following theorem ofDevlin and Shelah.

Theorem 3.1 [6]. The inequality 2ℵ0 < 2ℵ1 implies the following statement.For every F : 2<ω1 → 2 there is a g : ω1 → 2 such that, for every f : ω1 → 2,

{δ < ω1 : g(δ) = F(f � δ)}is stationary.

Applications of this theorem frequently involve some encoding and decoding ofcountable structures as countable binary sequences. This involves a fairly standardargument (cf. e.g. [9, II, Exer. (51)]; see also the proof of Lemma 4.11 to follow),but for concreteness I will state an equivalent formulation of Theorem 3.1.

Theorem 3.2. The inequality 2ℵ0 < 2ℵ1 implies the following statement. Forevery F : H(ℵ+0 ) → 2 there is a g : ω1 → 2 such that, for every A in H(ℵ+1 ),there exists a countable elementary submodel M of H(ℵ+1 ) with A in M such thatg(ωM

1 ) �= F(AM).

The following lemma, taken with Lemma 2.9, now completes Theorem 1.10.

The Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders 443

Lemma 3.3. Suppose there is an Aronszajn tree T with the following properties:

(i) T is club-embeddable into all of its subtrees, and(ii) every ladder system coloring can be T -uniformized.

Then 2ℵ0 = 2ℵ1.

Proof. Suppose that T satisfies the hypotheses of the lemma. By replacing T

with an isomorphic tree if necessary, we may assume for simplicity that the ele-ments of T are in H(ℵ+0 ). Fix a ladder system 〈Cα : α ∈ lim(ω1)〉 and a functionτ : ω1 → T such that τ(α) has height α for each α < ω1. We will define a func-tion F : H(ℵ+0 ) → 2 that shows the conclusion of Theorem 3.2 to be false andhence that 2ℵ0 = 2ℵ1.

Suppose h is a club-endomorphism of T, as evidenced by a club E ⊆ ω1, andsuppose ϕ is a function (defined on the range of h) that takes values in ω. If M

is a countable elementary submodel of H(ℵ+1 ) that contains T, E, h, and ϕ and ifδ = M ∩ ω1, then

T M =⋃

α<δ

Tα ,

(E,h,ϕ)M = (E ∩ δ,h � T M,ϕ � T M).

If A = (E,h,ϕ) for some E, h, ϕ, and M as before, set F(AM) = i if and only if(iff ) ϕ[h(δ)] � Cδ ≡∗ i. Notice that, since E is a club and h is an endomorphismof T � E, this depends only on AM = (E ∩ δ,h � T M,ϕ � T M). If F is defined inthis way then we will say that F is defined nontrivially. On the rest of H(ℵ+0 ), setF equal to 0.

In order to finish the proof, I will show that for every g : ω1 → 2 there is anA = (E,h,ϕ) such that, if M is a countable elementary submodel of H(ℵ+1 ) withA in M, then F(AM) = g(ωM

1 ). Toward this end, let g be given and define �f byletting fα be the function with domain Cα that takes the constant value g(α). Nowapply (A) to find a subtree S of T and a function ϕ : S → 2 that uniformizes �f .

By assumption, there is a club E ⊆ ω1 and an order-preserving map h of T � E

into S � E. Put A = (E,h,ϕ) and let M be a countable elementary submodel ofH(ℵ+1 ) such that A is in M. It follows from our definitions and the choices madepreviously that F(AM) = g(ωM

1 ).

4. Iterating Proper Forcings without Adding Reals

In this section I will present the preservation lemmas to be used in Section 5. Theapproach will seem different than that used in the literature but is equivalent forour purposes. Part of my motivation for this departure is the hope that it makesthe tasks at hand more transparent.

First I review some definitions and theorems from [15]. Recall that a forcing isa transitive relation ≤ on a set Q that has a greatest element. Typically the sameletter is used to denote both the forcing and the underlying set. Elements of Q arereferred to as conditions and should be viewed as approximating a generic object

444 Justin Tatch Moore

that is being created by the forcing. In this paper, p ≤ q will mean that p is anextension of q; that is, p is a better approximation than q.

Shelah’s notion of a completeness system has served as a staple in proofs show-ing that certain countable support iterations do not introduce reals.

Definition 4.1 [15, V.5.2]. A completeness system for a forcing Q is a functionD such that the following statements hold.

(1) For a sufficiently large θ, the domain of D consists of pairs (M, q), where M

is a countable elementary submodel of H(θ) containing Q as an element andq is in Q ∩M.

(2) For every (M, q) in the domain of D, D(M, q) is a collection of subsets of

Gen(M, Q, q) = {G ⊆ Q ∩M : G is an M-generic filter}.Definition 4.2 [15, V.5.2]. If λ is a cardinal, then D is a λ-completeness sys-tem if, for every (M, q) in the domain of D, the intersection of fewer than 1+ λ

elements is nonempty.

Definition 4.3 [15,V.5.4]. A completeness system D for Q is said to be simpleif there is a second-order formula ψ such that D(M, q) = {GX : X ⊆ M}, where

GX = {G∈Gen(M, q) : (M, ∈ , Q ∩M) |= ψ[G,X]}.(A second-order formula allows quantification over both elements and subsets.)

Definition 4.4 [15,V.5.3]. Suppose that D is a simple completeness system fora forcing Q. Then Q is said to be D-complete if, for every (M, q) in the domainof D,

Gen+(M, Q, q) = {G∈Gen(M, Q, q) : M |= G has a lower bound}contains an element of D(M, q).

Theorem 4.5 [15, VIII.4.5]. A countable support iteration of forcings that areα-proper for all α < ω1 and D-complete with respect to a simple 2-completenesssystem does not introduce reals.

Remark 4.6. The concept of α-properness is defined in [15,V.3.1]. An equivalentformulation for forcings that do not introduce reals will be given in Definition 4.15.

I will now define an abstract completeness system and argue that it captures muchof the generality of the foregoing definitions. It will be useful to define a certaincategory to facilitate the discussion. First, expand the language of ZFC to adda predicate Q for a distinguished forcing. Let ZFCQ be the axioms of ZFC butwith the power set axiom replaced by “P(P(Q)) exists”. The objects of the cate-gory M are those countable transitive sets, together with a distinguished elementQM, that satisfy ZFCQ when Q is interpreted as QM. Note that if Q is a set andP(P(Q)) is in H(θ) for some θ, then H(θ) would be an element of M except thatit is not countable.

The Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders 445

An arrow−→MN in M is an elementary embedding ε : M → N with the property

that ε is in N and N satisfies “M = dom(ε) is countable”. The notation M →N will be used to denote

−→MN and also to assert the statement “

−→MN is an arrow

in M”. Observe that arrows fix hereditarily countable sets. Also, notation such asM → N is meaningful even if N is uncountable.

We will mostly consider commutative diagrams in M, so there will be at mostone arrow between two given objects. If M → N and if X is a subset of QM, thenX will simultaneously viewed as a subset of QN.

Definition 4.7. Suppose that N is a model of ZFCQ and that M is an elemen-tary submodel of N such that M is in N and N satisfies “M is countable”. Thenthere is a unique induced arrow M → N that commutes with the collapsing maps.

I am now ready to define the simple completeness system of interest. Suppose thatQ is a given forcing.

Definition 4.8. If θ is a regular cardinal, then a (Q, θ)-diagram is a diagramin M such that there exist (i) a minimum M in the order induced from the arrowsand (ii) an elementary embedding x �→ x from M into H(θ) that sends QM to Q.

The range of this embedding is a countable elementary submodel of H(θ), whichwill be denoted M. A diagram is a Q-diagram if it is a (Q, θ)-diagram for some θ.

Definition 4.9. Let M → N be a Q-diagram. If G ⊆ QM, then we will saythat G is

−→MN -prebounded if, whenever N → N and G is in N, N satisfies “G is

bounded in QN”.

Definition 4.10. A forcing Q is completely proper if there is a θ such that, forevery (Q, θ)-diagram of the form M → Ni (i < 2) and q in QM, there exists aG ⊆ QM that is M-generic, contains q, and is

−→MNi-prebounded for both i < 2.

Lemma 4.11. Every completely proper forcing is 2-complete with respect to somesimple completeness system D.

Remark 4.12. Of course, there is a canonical definition of λ-completely properfor each λ ≤ ℵ1. The results in the remainder of this section are easily adapted tothis greater generality, but at present I see no reason to seek such generality. Theterminology completely proper is sometimes given the same meaning as totallyproper. I have chosen the present usage since it is more closely tied to Shelah’susage of “completeness” and since “totally proper” seems more established in theliterature.

Proof of Lemma 4.11. Let Q be a completely proper forcing and let θ be largeenough to exhibit this. Suppose M is a countable elementary submodel of H(θ)

that has Q as an element. If M → N, define G−→MN

to be the set of all G ∈Gen(M, Q, q) such that πG is

−→MN -prebounded. Here π is the collapsing isomor-

phism for M, the image of M under its embedding into H(θ). Define D(M, q) tobe the collection of all G−→

MNas−→MN ranges over the arrows in M.

446 Justin Tatch Moore

Clearly D is a completeness system and Q is 2-complete with respect to it; henceit suffices to show that D is simple. Though we are not allowed explicit quantifica-tion over arrows in the definition of “simple”, this can be achieved by appropriatecoding. For instance, there is a second-order formula ψ0 such that, if X ⊆ M and

(M, ∈ , QM) |= ψ0[X]

and we define RX = {p ∈M : (0,p) ∈ X} and ιX = {p ∈M : (1,p) ∈ X}, then(ω,RX,Q) is a well-founded model of ZFCQ and ιX is an elementary embeddingfrom (M, ∈ , QM) into (ω,RX,Q). This takes care of the assertion that N is in M

and M → N; one can similarly handle the quantification over N → N.

It is also worth noting that it is possible to prove a partial converse to Lemma 4.11.

Definition 4.13. Q is said to have the effective bounding property if, wheneverQ0 is a countable subset of Q, the set of all G ⊆ Q0 such that G has a lowerbound in Q is a Borel subset of P(Q0).

Many forcings (including those in the next section) have this property, and thiscondition is readily verified by inspection.

Lemma 4.14. If Q has the effective bounding property and is D-complete withrespect to some simple 2-completeness system D, then Q is completely proper.

Proof. Let ψ be the formula used to define D and let θ0 be the sufficiently largeregular cardinal witnessing that D is a 2-completeness system. Let θ be such thatH(θ0) is in H(θ). Now suppose that M → Ni (i < 2) is a given (Q, θ)-diagramand that q is in QM. Notice that, for a given i < 2, Ni satisfies “ψ defines a simple2-completeness system witnessing that Q is D-complete”. In particular, if MNi

is the image of M under the embedding M → Ni, then Gen+(M, Q, q)Ni con-tains an element YNi of D(M, q)Ni as a subset. Furthermore, Gen+(M, Q, q)Ni isa Borel subset of (Q ∩ M )Ni because Ni satisfies “QNi has the effective boundingproperty”.

There are two sets in H(θ) that correspond to Gen+(M, Q, q)Ni. One is a (count-able) subset of Ni and the other is a (typically uncountable) Borel set XNi obtainedby interpreting Ni’s Borel code for Gen+(M, Q, q)Ni. Let εi : MNi → M for i <

2 be the unique elementary isomorphisms, and put X i = {εiH : H ∈ XNi } andYi = {εiH : H ∈ YNi }. Observe that Yi is in D(M, q) by the elementarity of εiapplied to ψ. Since D is a 2-completeness system, it follows that Y0∩Y1 containsan element H ⊆ Q ∩ M. Let G ⊆ QM be the image of H under M’s collapsingisomorphism.

Now suppose that i < 2. To see that G is−→MNi-prebounded, let Ni → N be

such that G is in N. For any X ⊆ (Q ∩ M )Ni that is in N, εiX is in X i iff X is inXNi iff N satisfies “X is in Gen+(M, Q, q)N ”. Therefore, N satisfies “ε−1

i H is inGen+(M, Q, q)N ” and hence also that “G is bounded in QN ”. (In the latter quo-tation I am identifying G with its image under the embedding of M into N; this isnot the case in the former quotation.)

The Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders 447

Traditionally, completeness with respect to a simple completeness system needsto be supplemented with <ω1-properness in order to obtain preservation resultsfor not adding reals. While total <ω1-properness is a standard notion in this con-text [15, V.3.1], the following definition gives an equivalent formulation in termsof diagrams.

Definition 4.15. A forcing Q is totally <ω1-proper if, whenever Mξ → Mη

(ξ < η ≤ γ ) is an amenable Q-diagram for γ < ω1 and q is in QM0 , there existsa q in Q such that q ≤ q and q is totally (M, Q)-generic for all ξ ≤ γ—that is, thefilter {p ∈QMξ : q ≤ p} is Mξ -generic. (Here, amenable means that, wheneverη ≤ γ is a limit, limξ→η Mξ = Mη and 〈Mξ : ξ < η〉 ∈Mη+1 if η + 1≤ γ.)

The following lemma is now an immediate consequence of the previous observa-tions and [15, VIII.4.5].

Lemma 4.16. A countable support iteration of completely proper, <ω1-properforcings does not introduce reals.

I will now finish this section with a condition that is essentially a reformulation ofShelah’s properness isomorphism condition. The condition is made useful by thefollowing theorem.

Theorem 4.17 [15, VIII.2.4]. If P is a countable support iteration of lengthat most ω2 whose iterands satisfy the properness isomorphism condition ( p.i.c.),then P satisfies the ℵ2-chain condition.

Theorem VIII.2.4 of [15] states something stronger and more general; in partic-ular, the ℵ2-p.i.c. is a consequence of the conventional properness isomorphismcondition stated in Definition 4.18.

Definition 4.18. A forcing Q satisfies the properness isomorphism condition if,whenever

(i) Mi (i < 2) are countable elementary submodels of H(θ) for θ a sufficientlylarge cardinal number,

(ii) ϕ : M0 → M1 is an isomorphism that fixes M0 ∩ M1 and Q in M0 ∩ M1, and(iii) q is in Q ∩ M0,

there is a q that extends both q and ϕ(q) and that is (Mi, Q)-generic for each i < 2.

The following condition is formally stronger than the properness isomorphismcondition, but it seems likely to be the same in practice.

Definition 4.19. Q is said to have the strong chain condition (this is an ad hocname and not intended for long-term use) if (a) whenever M

εi−→ N (i < 2) is aQ-diagram and q is in QM, there is a G ⊆ QM that is M-generic and (b) when-ever N → N is an arrow in M and G is in N, there is a q in QN that is a lowerbound for εiG.

448 Justin Tatch Moore

Remark 4.20. The difference between the strong chain condition and completeproperness is that in the strong chain condition only pairs of “top models” that areequal are considered—but with the added requirement that, if this common modelis extended to pick up G, then there is a single bound for both images of G in thisextension.

Lemma 4.21. The strong chain condition implies the properness isomorphismcondition.

Proof. This is similar to the arguments already given. I will leave the proof to theinterested reader.

Combining Theorem 4.17 and Lemma 4.21, we now have the following lemma.

Lemma 4.22. A countable support iteration of length ω2 of forcings with thestrong chain condition over a ground model that satisfies CH has the ℵ2 chaincondition and, in particular, preserves cardinals that are at least ℵ2.

5. How to Uniformize Colorings Relative to anAronszajn Tree and Not Introduce Reals

In this section I will prove Theorem 1.9. For the moment, let T be a fixed Arons-zajn tree, let 〈Cα : α ∈ lim(ω1)〉 be a fixed ladder system, and let �f = 〈fα : α ∈lim(ω1)〉 be a coloring of 〈Cα : α ∈ lim(ω1)〉. For simplicity we may and will as-sume that T is a subtree of ω<ω1 , the collection of all countable length sequencesfrom ω ordered by extension. This has the added benefit of causing elements of Tto be fixed by the arrows discussed in the previous section.

Definition 5.1. If n < ω, let T [n] denote the subset of T n of all σ such that, forall i < j < n, σ(i) has the same height as σ(j) and σ(i) ≤ σ(j) in the lexico-graphical ordering. If an element of T [n] is one-to-one, then it will be identifiedwith its range without further mention. A finite power of T is a set of the formT [n] for some n < ω.

Definition 5.2. Let σ be in a finite power of T and let X be a subset of T con-sisting of elements of height at most α with X∩Tα �= ∅. Then σ is consistent withX if σ � α is a subset of X. Also, we say that two functions f and g are consistentif they agree on the intersection of their domains.

Definition 5.3. Let Q = Q( �f ; T ) be the collection of all q = (ϕ, U ) such thatthe following statements hold.

(1) There is a minimal α = αq such that the domain of ϕ (denoted X = Xq) is adownwards closed subset of T consisting of elements of height at most α.

(2) U is a nonempty countable collection such that, if U is in U , then U is a prunedsubtree of a finite power of T.

(3) For every U in U , there is a σ in U of height α that is consistent with X.

(4) ϕ is a function from the elements of X of height less than α into ω such that,if s is an element of X of limit height ν, then fν =∗ ϕ[s] � Cν.

The Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders 449

Notation 5.4. If q is in Q, then (ϕq , Uq) will be used to denote q. Here Q ismade into a forcing notion by saying that q extends p if ϕp is an initial part of ϕq

and Up ⊆ Uq .

Lemma 5.5. Suppose that M is a countable elementary submodel of H(2ℵ+1 ) and

let δ = M ∩ ω1. For every q in Q ∩ M, every dense open D ⊆ Q in M, and everyfinite σ ⊆ Tδ that is consistent with q, there exists a q ≤ q in D such that σ isconsistent with q.

Proof. Suppose this is not the case and let M, q, D, and σ be counterexamples. Letn denote the cardinality of σ. Since Tδ is countable, there is a function τ : ω1 →T [n] in M such that τ(δ) = σ and τ(ξ) has height ξ for all ξ < ω1. Let 4 be theset of all ξ < ω1 such that, if q ≤ q, q is in D, and αq < ξ, then τ(ξ) is not con-sistent with q. Observe that 4 is in M. I now claim that δ is in 4. To see this,suppose q ≤ q is in D and ν = αq < δ. Then σ is consistent with q iff σ � ν is.Since σ � ν is in M, if σ were consistent with q then we could find such a q in M.

But this would contradict our assumptions on M, q, D, and σ.

Now let U be the set of all υ such that, for uncountably many ξ in 4, υ ≤ τ(ξ).

It is routine to verify that U is uncountable, pruned, and downwards closed. I shallobtain a contradiction by arguing that (ϕq , Uq ∪ {U}) has no extension in D. If itdid, let q be such an extension and pick a σ0 ⊆ Xq ∩U of height αq . By construc-tion, there is a ξ in 4 such that σ0 = τ(ξ) � αq . But this would imply that τ(ξ) isconsistent with q, contradicting the definition of 4.

Definition 5.6. Suppose that q and q are in Q. Then q is said to be a conserva-tive extension of q if q ≤ q and, whenever σ is a finite subset of T that is consistentwith q, σ is consistent with q.

Lemma 5.7. For every β, every q in Q, and every finite partial function ψ : T →ω that is consistent with ϕq , there is a conservative extension q of q such that β ≤αq and ψ is consistent with ϕq . In particular, every condition in Q forces that:

(5) the union U of Xq (q ∈ G) is uncountable and hence is a subtree of T ; and(6) the union ϕ of the first coordinates of elements of G is a uniformizing function

for �f that is defined on U.

Proof. Let β and ψ be fixed and suppose that q is in Q. By making β larger ifnecessary, we may assume that β is an upper bound on the heights of elements ofthe domain of ψ. If β ≤ αq , then q = q works. Now suppose that αq < β and letr : lim(β + 1)→ β be a regressive function such that

{Cξ \ r(ξ) : ξ ∈ lim(β + 1)}is a pairwise disjoint family whose union does not contain the heights of any ele-ment of the domain of ψ. Let

Xq = {s ∈ T≤β : s � α ∈Xq},U q = Uq ,

and define ϕq on those elements of Xq of height less than β by

450 Justin Tatch Moore

(7) ϕq(s) = ϕq(s) if s is in Xq ,(8) ϕq(s) = fν(ξ) if ξ ≥ αq is the height of s and if ν satisfies ξ ∈Cν \ r(ν),(9) ϕq(s) = ψ(s) if s is in the domain of ψ, and

(10) ϕq(s) = 0 otherwise.

It is left to the reader to verify that q is a condition in Q and that it is a conserva-tive extension of q. Observe, however, that this is where we need the requirementthat the elements of Uq be pruned.

The following lemma will be useful in demonstrating that a given generic filterhas a lower bound in a larger model.

Lemma 5.8. Suppose that M → N is a Q-diagram and that G ⊆ QM is M-generic. Then G is

−→MN -prebounded if the following conditions are satisfied: for

every U in⋃

p∈G Up, there exist a σ in UN of height δ = ωM1 and a δ0 < δ such

that, for every p in G, σ is consistent with p and ϕp(s � ξ) = f Nδ (ξ) whenever s

is in σ and ξ is in CNδ with δ0 < ξ ≤ αp.

Proof. Let M, N, and G be as given in the statement of the lemma and supposethat the conditions are satisfied by G. Suppose that N → N is given. Working inN, set

X =⋃

p∈GXp, U q =

p∈GUp, ϕq =

p∈Gϕp.

Let Xq be the union of X with the set of all s in Tδ such that every predecessor ofs is in X and, for all but finitely many ξ in Cδ , ϕ(s � ξ) = fδ(ξ). If U is in U q

then, by assumption, there is a σ in U of height δ such that σ ⊆ Xq. Hence q is a

condition in QN that, moreover, is clearly a lower bound for G.

Observe that the bound q produced by Lemma 5.8 has the following property:whenever σ is an element of a finite power of T that is consistent with every p inG, then σ is consistent with q provided that, for all but finitely many ξ in CN

δ \ δ0,ϕq(s � ξ) = f N

δ (ξ)

for all s ∈ σ. If, moreover, αq = δ, then q is unique and will be referred to as theconservative bound for G.

The relevant properties of Q will be proved by iterating the following lemmawith appropriate “bookkeeping”.

Lemma 5.9. Suppose that M → Ni (i ≤ k) is a Q-diagram, q is in QM, U is inUM

q , D ⊆ Q is dense open and in M, and σi (i < k) and νi (i ≤ k) satisfy thefollowing conditions:

(11) for each i < k, νi is an ordinal with ωM1 ≤ νi < ω

Ni

1 ;(12) for each i < k, σi is an element of a finite power of T Ni of height νi that is

consistent with q; and(13) {σi � αq : i < k} is a pairwise disjoint family.

The Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders 451

Then there exist a σk and a q ≤ q in DM such that:

(14) σk is in UNk and has height νk;(15) for all i ≤ k, σi is consistent with q;(16) {σi � αq : i ≤ k} is a pairwise disjoint family; and(17) if i < k, ξ is in CNi

νiwith αq ≤ ξ < αq , and s is in σi, then ϕq(s � ξ) =

f Niνi

(ξ).

Proof. Let M → Ni (i ≤ k), q, U, D as well as σi (i < k) and νi (i ≤ k) be asgiven in the statement of the lemma, and let α denote αq. Select a P ∈M suchthat M satisfies “P is an elementary submodel of H(2ℵ

+1 ) such that q and DM are

in P ”. Let F be the set of all s � ξ such that, for some i < k, s is in σi and ξ is inP ∩ CNi

νi\ α. Let ψ denote the function with domain F defined by

s � ξ �→ f Niνi

(ξ)

if s is in σi. Note that, by (13), ψ is well-defined.Applying Lemma 5.7 in P to ψ and to a β that bounds the heights in F, there is

a q ′ ≤ q in P that is a conservative extension of q such that ϕq ′ extends ψ. Putting

υ =⋃

i<k

σi � (P ∩ ω1),

we can apply Lemma 5.5 to obtain a q ′′ ≤ q ′ in P such that q ′′ is in DM ∩ P andυ is consistent with q ′′.

I now need to construct σk. Let τ be an element of U of height αq ′′ that is inXq ′′ . Let n denote the cardinality of υ. By [19, Lemma 5.9] applied in P, thereexist υj (j < n + 1) in U ∩ P such that (a) each extends τ and (b) if j �= j ′ <n+1, then no element of υj is comparable with any element of υj ′ . Notice that ifs is in υ then there is at most one j < n+1 such that s is comparable with an ele-ment of υj . Hence there is an l < n + 1 such that no element of υ is compatiblewith any element of υl. Since U is pruned, there is a σk in UNk

νkthat extends υ

Nk

l .

Finally, use Lemma 5.7 to find a q in P that is a conservative extension of q ′′ suchthat αq is greater than the height of υl and hence (16) holds. Since ϕq ′′ extends ψ

and sinceCNi

νi∩ P = CNi

νi∩ αq ′′

for all i < k, it follows that (17) holds. Since υ is consistent with q ′′, so is each σi

(i < k). This finishes the proof.

We will now see that Q satisfies conditions that are sufficient to ensure it can beiterated while preserving cardinality and not introducing reals.

Lemma 5.10. The forcing Q is completely proper and satisfies the strong chaincondition.

Proof. First I will show that Q is completely proper. Let M → Nk (k < 2) bea Q-diagram and let q ∈QM. Fix an enumeration Di (i < ω) of all dense opensubsets of Q in M and an enumeration with infinite repetition (Ui, ki) (i < ω) of

452 Justin Tatch Moore

all pairs (U, k) such that U is a subtree of a finite power of T, U is in M, and k <

2. Using Lemma 5.9, construct a decreasing sequence q(i) (i < ω) of conditionsin QM that are below q and a sequence of σ(i) (i < ω) such that, for all j < ω:

(18) q(j) is in DMj ;

(19) if Uj is in Uq(j), then σ(j) is in UNkjj and of height δ = ωM

1 ;(20) {σ(i) � αq(j) : i < j} is a pairwise disjoint family;(21) if i < ω, then σ(i) is consistent with q(j); and(22) if i < j, s is in σ(i), and ξ is in CNk i

δ with αq(i) < ξ < αq(j), then we haveϕq(j)(s � ξ) = f Nk i

δ (ξ).

Let G be the set of all p in QM such that there is an i < ω with q(i) ≤ p.

Clearly G is M-generic. Now suppose that k < 2 is given. To see that G is−→MNk-

prebounded, it is sufficient to verify the hypotheses of Lemma 5.8. Toward thisend, suppose that U is in

⋃p∈G Up. Pick an i < ω such that U is in Uq(i), Ui =

U, and ki = k. Set δ0 = αq(i) and let p be any element of G. Pick a j ≥ i suchthat q(j) ≤ p. By construction, q(j) is consistent with σ and hence so is p. If sis in σ, δ0 < ξ ≤ αp ≤ αq(j), and ξ is in CNk

δ , then

ϕp(s � ξ) = ϕq(j)(s � ξ) = fNk

δ (ξ).

By Lemma 5.8, I am now finished.To see that Q has the strong chain condition, proceed as before with N0 = N1 =

N in order to construct G ⊆ QM. Now let N → N be given such that G is in N

and let εi denote the arrows witnessing M → Ni. Let qi be the conservative lowerbound of εiG and observe that ϕq0 = ϕq1; let ϕq = ϕq0 = ϕq1. Similarly, if U isin U qi then there is a U ′ in U q1−i

, which are equal when restricted to their elementsof height less than δ; let U q = U q0 ∪ U q1. It is easily verified that q is now the de-sired bound.

Lemma 5.11. Q is totally <ω1-proper.

Proof. Let γ < ω1 be given and fix an amenable Q-diagram Mη → Mζ (η <

ζ ≤ γ ). Following the methods of Lemma 5.10, we will construct a decreasingsequence qζ (ζ ≤ γ ) in Q by recursion in such a way that, if ζ is a limit, then qζ

is the conservative lower bound for qη (η < ζ).

For now, let us focus on the successor stages. Fix an enumeration Di (i < ω)

of all dense open subsets of Q in Mγ and an enumeration (Ui, ζi) (i < ω) withinfinite repetition such that, for each i, Ui is a subtree of a finite power of T corre-sponding to an element of Mγ and ζi ≤ γ is a limit ordinal. Also fix a well-order! of H(ℵ+1 ) that is in M0 and that well-orders γ in type ω. If ζ ≤ γ, let mζ be thenumber of η ≤ γ such that η ! ζ.

Now suppose that qζ is given. Using Lemma 5.9, construct a decreasing se-quence qζ(i) (i < ω) of conditions in QMζ+1 that are below qζ and a sequence ofσζ(i) (i < ω) such that the following conditions hold.

(23) qζ(i) = qζ if i < mζ .

(24) If DMζ+1i is in Mζ+1, then qζ(mζ + i) is in DMζ+1

i .

The Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders 453

(25) If Ui is in Uqζ(i) and ζ ≤ ζi, then σζ(i) is in UMζi+1i and of height νi = ω

Mζi1 .

(26) For all k < ω, {σζ(i) � αqζ(k) : i < k} is a pairwise disjoint family.(27) For all i, j, σζ(i) is consistent with qζ(j).

(28) If i < k, s is in σζ(i), and ξ is in CMζiνi

with αqζ(i) < ξ < αqζ(k), then we haveϕ(s � ξ) = fMζi

νi(ξ).

(29) Given that the construction has been carried out for all i < k, it follows thatqζ(k) and σζ(k) are the !-least objects satisfying conditions (23)–(28).

Arguing as in Lemma 5.10, the sequence qζ(i) (i < ω) generates an Mζ+1-genericfilter. Note that 〈qζ(i) : i < ω〉 is in Mζ+1 by the recursion theorem (see [9,III.5.6]), so applying Lemma 5.8 shows that the conservative lower bound qζ+1

of this sequence is in Mζ+1.

Now suppose that ζ is a limit ordinal. It is clear that {qη : η < ζ} generates anMζ -generic filter. There are two obstacles to overcome: we need to show that thisfilter is in Mζ+1 and that it has a lower bound in Mζ+1. The first claim follows fromthe recursion theorem and the fact that, at each point of the recursion, we chose!-minimal witnesses.

Now it remains to verify the hypothesis of Lemma 5.8. The key observation isas follows.

Claim 5.12. If mζ0 < mη whenever ζ0 < η < ζ, then ση(i) = σζ0(i) for alli < mζ0 .

Proof. Suppose this is not the case and let (η, i) be the lexicographically leastcounterexample. Observe that qη is consistent with σζ0(i) because qη is the con-servative lower bound for qη ′(k) (η ′ < η and k < ω). By the minimality of i,ση(i

′) = σζ0(i′) for all i ′ < i and so it is easily checked that σζ0(i) satisfies the

conditions of the recursion (except possibly its !-minimality). Notice, however,that if σ satisfies the conditions for ση(i) then it does also for σζ0(i), since theconditions qη(k) (k < ω) are stronger than any of the conditions qζ0(k) (k < ω).

Since σζ0(i) was taken to be !-minimal, it must be that ση(i) = σζ0(i).

In order to verify the hypotheses of Lemma 5.8, let U be an element of⋃

η<ζ Uqη .

Let i be such that Ui = U and ζi = ζ, and find a ζ0 < ζ such that i < mζ0 if ζ0 ≤η < ζ ; then mζ0 < mη.

Now suppose that ξ is in Cζ \ αqζ and let s be in σi. Let η be the least ordinalsuch that ξ < αqη+1, noting that then αqη < ξ. By arrangement, i < mη and there-fore αqη(mη−1) ≤ ξ, since qη = qη(mη−1). Because there exists a k < ω such thatξ < αqη(k), (28) implies that

ϕqη(k)(s � ξ) = fζ(ξ)

as desired. Lemma 5.8 now implies that qη (η < ζ) has a unique conservativelower bound qζ in Mζ+1.

We are now ready to finish the proof of Theorem 1.9. Let V be a given groundmodel. By doing a preliminary proper forcing if necessary, we may assume thatVsatisfies 2ℵ0 = ℵ1 and 2ℵ1 = ℵ2. InV, build a countable support iteration of length

454 Justin Tatch Moore

ω2 such that all of the iterands are forced to be of the form Q( �f ; T ) and, following[17] (or [9, VIII.6]), in such a way that, by the end of the iteration, Q( �f ; T ) hasbeen forced with at some initial stage whenever �f and T are appropriate elementsof the final generic extension (this is possible by the ground model assumptionsand Lemma 4.22). By Lemma 5.7, Q( �f ; T ) forces that the coloring �f can beT -uniformized. Hence the final model satisfies (A). It follows from Lemmas 4.16and 4.22 that the resulting iteration preserves cardinals and does not introducereals. The latter consequence implies that the final extension satisfies CH.

6. Closing Remarks

I will finish this paper with some remarks and further consequences of the resultsso far. In Section 1 it was noted that, in hindsight, a more conventional approachto the main result should work. In particular, if we let Q(T ) be the forcing thatconsists of the pairs q = (Xq , Uq), as in the definition of Q(T ; �f ), then Q(T ) in-troduces a subtree U of T into which T does not club-embed. Moreover, Q(T )

can be iterated without adding reals. It seems likely that countable support itera-tions of forcings of this type preserve that U does not club-embed into T, thoughthis probably involves a rather tedious argument if proved directly. This methodwould also not be as “portable” to future applications; see the further discussionat the end of this section.

Now consider the following theorem in relation to Theorem 1.7.

Theorem 6.1. Let C be a fixed Countryman line. The assertion that C is mini-mal can be made either true or false by proper forcing but cannot be changed byσ-closed forcing.

In particular,♦+ does not imply that all minimal Aronszajn lines are Souslin. Thispartially addresses Baumgartner’s question of whether his construction necessar-ily produces Souslin lines. The invariance of the minimality of C under σ-closedforcing is essentially due to Baumgartner [5]. Since MA(ℵ1) can always be forcedby a proper (even countable chain condition) forcing [17], any Countryman linecan be made minimal by proper forcing. On the other hand, Theorem 1.9 assertsthat the conjunction of (A) and CH can be made true by proper forcing; by thesubsequent theorems, this conjunction implies that C is not minimal.

We also have an example related to the following problem of Woodin. Thereader is referred to [22] for undefined terminology.

Question 6.2 [22]. Are there �2-sentences ϕ1 and ϕ2 such that

(H(ℵ+1 ), ∈) |= CH ∧ ϕ1 and

(H(ℵ+1 ), ∈) |= CH ∧ ϕ2

are each =-consistent but whose conjunction =-implies the negation of CH?

This question is motivated by Woodin’s celebrated result of [22] that the answeris negative if CH is replaced by ZFC. This offers an explanation of the observed

The Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders 455

phenomenon that every forcible �2-sentence about H(ℵ+1 ) can be proved if oneassumes a strong enough forcing axiom and, in particular, that all such sentencesare mutually consistent. Whether the same can be said about the stronger theoryZFC+ CH is the content of this question.

Let LC be the expansion of the usual language L of set theory to include a pred-icate �C, and add an axiom asserting that �C is a C-sequence of length ω1—that is,Cα is a cofinal subset of α for every α < ω1, and if γ < α then Cα ∩ γ is finite.Such an extension of the language is not entirely contrived, since the analysis ofminimal walks on ω1 is based around a fixed C-sequence that is used to constructa number of 2-place “>-functions”. These have served as a unified approach tocombinatorial constructions at this level (see [21]).

Theorem 6.3. There are two �2-sentences ϕ1 and ϕ2 in L and LC , respectively,such that

(H(ℵ+1 ), ∈) |= CH ∧ ϕ1 and

(H(ℵ+1 ), ∈ , �C) |= CH ∧ ϕ2

are each =-consistent but ϕ1 ∧ ϕ2 implies 2ℵ0 = 2ℵ1.

Theorem 6.1 also yields the following result, which is related to Steel’s questionon the ?2

2-completeness of ♦ and attendant assertions.

Theorem 6.4. There is a ?2-sentence ψ in LC such that

(H(ℵ+1 ), ∈ , �C) |= ψ

is =-independent although ψ is invariant under σ-closed forcing.

Question 6.5. Is there a ?2-sentence ψ in the language of (H(ℵ+1 ), ∈) that is=-independent but invariant under σ-closed forcing?

Arguing as in [1, 2.3], Larson has noted that there exist Tx and subtrees Sx ⊆ Tx

indexed by 2ω1 such that: (i) each Tx ⊆ ω<ω1 is coherent, is closed under finitechanges, and consists of finite-to-one functions; and (ii) if x �= y and if ζ is theleast ordinal such that x(ζ) �= y(ζ), then

(Tx)ζ = (Ty)ζ ,

(Sx)ζ ∩ (Sy)ζ = ∅.This can be used with Lemma 2.9, Theorem 3.1, and [19, Thm. 3.4] to show thatif 2ℵ0 < 2ℵ1 then there is a Countryman line that is not minimal. Hence it is notpossible to remove the predicate in the previous examples by quantifying over allsuch C-sequences.

Finally, let us finish with the following question.

Question 6.6. Is the forcing axiom for completely proper forcings (CPFA) con-sistent with CH relative to a large cardinal assumption?

The example of [15, XVIII.1] shows that some care needs to be taken in any ap-proach to this question but does not suggest a negative answer. A positive answerwould suggest a negative answer to Question 6.2.

456 Justin Tatch Moore

While the conjunction of CPFA and CH is not known to be consistent, substan-tial fragments of CPFA are consistent with CH and there is a considerable bodyof literature surrounding this (see [2; 7; 15]). Observe that we have accomplishedtwo tasks in this paper:

(1) the demonstration that the conjunction of CPFA and CH implies that ω1 and−ω1 are the only minimal uncountable ordertypes; and

(2) that this conclusion requires only the fragment of CPFA that is known to beconsistent with CH.

In recent joint work with Ishiu, Question 1.3 has been essentially reduced to Ques-tion 6.6.

Theorem 6.7 [8]. The conjunction of CPFA+ and CH implies that there are nominimal non-σ-scattered ordertypes.

References

[1] U. Abraham and S. Shelah, Isomorphism types of Aronszajn trees, Israel J. Math. 50(1985), 75–113.

[2] U. Abraham and S. Todorcevic, Partition properties of ω1 compatible with CH, Fund.Math. 152 (1997), 165–181.

[3] J. E. Baumgartner, All ℵ1-dense sets of reals can be isomorphic, Fund. Math. 79(1973), 101–106.

[4] , Order types of real numbers and other uncountable orderings, Orderedsets (Banff, 1981), NATO Adv. Sci. Inst. Ser. C Math. Phys. Sci., 83, pp. 239–277,Reidel, Dordrecht, 1982.

[5] , Bases for Aronszajn trees, Tsukuba J. Math. 9 (1985), 31–40.[6] K. Devlin and S. Shelah, A weak version of ♦ which follows from 2ℵ0 < 2ℵ1, Israel J.

Math. 29 (1978), 239–247.[7] T. Eisworth and J. Roitman, CH with no Ostaszewski spaces, Trans. Amer. Math.

Soc. 351 (1999), 2675–2693.[8] T. Ishiu and J. T. Moore, Minimality of non σ-scattered orders (submitted), April

2007.[9] K. Kunen, An introduction to independence proofs, Stud. Logic Found. Math., 102,

North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1983.[10] R. Laver, On Fraïssé’s order type conjecture, Ann. of Math. (2) 93 (1971), 89–111.[11] S. MacLane, Categories for the working mathematician, 2nd ed., Grad. Texts in

Math., 5, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1998.[12] J. T. Moore, A five element basis for the uncountable linear orders, Ann. of Math.

(2) 163 (2006), 669–688.[13] S. Shelah, Infinite abelian groups, Whitehead problem and some constructions, Israel

J. Math. 18 (1974), 243–256.[14] , Decomposing uncountable squares to countably many chains, J. Combin.

Theory Ser. A 21 (1976), 110–114.[15] , Proper and improper forcing, 2nd ed., Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1998.[16] W. Sierpinski, Sur un problème concernant les types de dimensions, Fund. Math. 19

(1932), 65–71.[17] R. Solovay and S. Tennenbaum, Iterated Cohen extensions and Souslin’s problem,

Ann. of Math. (2) 94 (1971), 201–245.

The Only Minimal Uncountable Linear Orders 457

[18] S. Todorcevic, Trees and linearly ordered sets, Handbook of set-theoretic topology,pp. 235–293, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1984.

[19] , Partitioning pairs of countable ordinals, Acta Math. 159 (1987), 261–294.[20] , Lipschitz maps on trees, report 2000/01, number 13, Institut Mittag-Leffler.[21] , Coherent sequences, Handbook of set theory, North-Holland, Amsterdam

(to appear).[22] W. H. Woodin, The axiom of determinacy, forcing axioms, and the nonstationary

ideal, de Gruyter Ser. Log. Appl. 1, de Gruyter, Berlin, 1999.

Department of MathematicsCornell University555 Malott HallIthaca, NY 14853-4201

[email protected]