῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

download ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

of 15

Transcript of ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    1/15

    'Epc,'E7rmOu,ta,

    nd

    acxa

    in Plato

    DREW A. HYLAND

    The encomium

    proper

    is

    preceded by a

    preliminary dialectical discussion with

    Agathon, the

    object of which is to clear the ground of some popular misconcep-

    tions of the

    nature

    of Eros.

    The

    notion of

    Eros, it is

    shown, is equivalent to that

    of

    desire

    (Ipcoq

    =

    s6

    &iwLOuIAo5v)

    ..

    a

    quality, not

    a

    person.

    Bury, R. G. The

    Symposium

    of

    Plato, page

    XXXVI-XXXVII, in a discussion of Socrates'

    speech.

    The subject of

    conversation (in the Lysis) is

    friendship (qX(a). But behind

    this word,

    it is

    clear,

    as will

    be

    briefly sketched,

    hides

    the

    more

    powerful

    Eros...

    There is hardly

    any terminological distinction

    between

    love

    and friendship,

    so

    that, first,

    desire

    is

    said

    to wish

    that

    of

    which

    it is

    in

    want,

    and then

    that

    the

    congenial

    be the

    object

    of

    'love, friendship,

    and desire'

    (,roil

    IxkLou

    6

    re

    Epwqxal

    h

    cpLXEa

    al

    t

    sIouFdm

    'ryX&vyL

    5av,

    221

    E).

    Friedlander, Paul, Plato, An Introduction,

    page

    50-51.

    is

    the purpose

    of this

    essay

    to take some

    first steps

    towarddis-

    pelling

    the

    popular conception, exemplified

    by

    the

    two above

    quotations,

    that there

    is

    little

    or no

    difference

    in

    Plato's

    dialogues

    between the

    three important terms

    Epwq,

    eTctE,

    and

    ptL?.1

    I

    say

    first

    steps

    because

    the vast

    number

    of

    significant

    occurrences

    of

    these terms

    in

    the dialogues

    makes

    it

    impossible

    to

    give

    an ex-

    haustive

    treatment in one short paper.

    Consequently,

    I

    propose

    to

    do the

    following: first,

    I

    shall elicit the

    relevant distinctions

    between

    these

    terms, and

    the basis for the distinctions,by a carefulexamination

    of

    two

    significant passages, Symposium

    200a-201b,

    and

    Lysis

    221-222.

    I

    shall attempt

    to show therein that

    although indeed these terms

    have an

    important connection with each other, nevertheless there

    1

    D. N. Levin, Some Observations Concerning Plato's Lysis , (presented at a

    meeting of the Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy,

    Amherst, Massachusetts,

    August 17, 1964), notes several different positions

    taken on the

    controversy

    (see especially pages 12-18 including footnotes), and

    he himself seems to come

    out in favor of some distinction at least between

    'Epcog

    and

    yWLX(

    (pages

    15-17)

    However, since the distinction in question is not the

    central theme of his

    essay,

    he does not offer decisive evidence for his view. I propose to do so in this essay.

    32

    Source: Phronesis, Vol. 13, No. 1 (1968), pp. 32-46

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    2/15

    are distinct

    and

    significant

    differences.

    I

    shall

    then consider several

    relevant passages

    from other dialogues

    in which

    I find the distinctions

    I draw supported.

    My

    claim

    is

    not,

    indeed cannot

    be,

    that

    Plato

    always

    consistently distinguishes

    the terms in

    question,

    that he never

    uses

    them

    interchangeably.

    To do so would necessitate

    a consideration

    of

    every

    occurrence

    of one

    or more of these terms

    in the

    dialogues.

    Besides,

    there are

    undoubtedly

    contexts in which

    such

    subtle

    distinc-

    tions

    are

    entirely

    irrelevant to the

    point being

    made.

    In

    such

    cases,

    need we

    doubt the

    sincerity

    or the wisdom

    of

    Socrates' words in

    the

    Theaetetus

    that

    To use words and

    phrases

    in an

    easy-going

    way

    without scrutinizing

    them too

    seriously

    is

    not,

    in

    general,

    a

    mark of

    ill breeding; on the contrary there is something lowbred in being too

    precise. 2

    Rather

    my

    more cautious claim will be that

    in

    at

    least

    several

    important passages

    where

    the distinctions

    would

    be

    relevant,

    Plato

    maintains them

    consistently. My

    suspicion

    is

    that

    this

    con-

    sistency

    is

    maintained

    more

    broadly;

    but this

    cannot be

    proved

    in a

    short

    paper. Finally,

    I

    shall

    offer a few

    suggestions

    as to

    possible

    philosophic consequences

    that

    would derive from a

    realization of

    these differences.

    Let me

    begin

    with the discussion

    between

    Socrates

    and

    Agathon at

    Symposium

    200a-201b.

    Socrates is concerned to

    show

    Agathon

    that

    'Epus

    is

    always

    directed,

    that

    is,

    it is

    always

    'Ep;

    of

    something

    and

    not

    in

    itself,

    and also that it

    is

    always

    of

    something

    which

    it lacks.

    I shall be concerned not

    so

    much

    with the

    establishing

    of

    these points

    as with the careful

    and distinct use of the terms

    in

    question.

    Let

    me

    first arrange

    the order

    of

    the

    argument,

    with

    special emphasis

    on the

    interchange

    of the relevant terms, then comment on the way in

    which the

    argument develops.

    The crucial passage

    begins

    at

    200a2

    when, having

    established

    that

    'Epco

    always

    has

    an

    object, Socrates

    asks

    Agathon

    to remember

    what he thinks the

    object

    to

    be,

    and

    then

    asks,

    Does

    'Epw;

    desire that of which it

    is

    'Epco? (o vEps 'exeLvou

    0o5

    I=v

    p@,

    Out& ouTo5 i

    o5;).

    This

    establishes what

    I

    shall cal

    for reference

    step

    one,

    that desire

    (&VnQua4x)

    s a

    possible predicate

    of

    'Epco.3

    '

    EpG.;desires. This thing that it desires and loves, does it

    desire

    and love it

    having

    it

    or

    not

    having

    it?

    (H6orepov

    cwv

    ocaur6

    i5

    2

    Plato, Theaetetus, 184c. Translation

    by F. M. Cornford.

    '

    I do not mean to imply by the

    use of the term steps that these are necessarily

    logical steps, that, say, step

    four

    follows

    logically

    from

    step three.

    I am simply

    distinguishing the stages

    in the

    argument

    relevant to

    my paper.

    33

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    3/15

    s7rLOu)e

    'r

    xaXpI,

    elZ'

    I

    tnUlIeZ

    xre X

    pI ,

    O-

    II

    oV;).4 Probably

    not

    having,

    says Agathon.

    This

    I shall

    call

    step two,

    that 'Epod

    both desires

    and loves,

    in other

    words,

    that love

    is in

    a

    way

    self-

    predicative,

    and that besides

    this it

    also

    desires.

    Consider,

    says

    Socrates,

    whether,

    rather than probable,

    it

    is

    not necessary

    that desire

    desires

    what

    it

    lacks,

    or does not desire

    if

    it

    does

    not

    lack.

    (x67nC

    8&1,

    vXL

    lo

    eLX6toq

    e

    M&vcyxz

    u'r

    0'

    Z'7rLOLouv

    OtWVLU.ZV

    Vi

    VW;

    '=LV,

    '

    'MtOU1?LV

    &&v

    -?

    C'

    ae;

    i;).5

    Here

    we

    have

    step

    three,

    which

    states

    only (as

    opposed

    to

    step

    two) that

    desire

    desires

    what it lacks.

    An

    important

    element

    in step

    three then,

    is

    that

    it

    says

    nothing

    explicitly

    about

    'Epw;.

    To this Agathon

    assents.

    Socrates next enters upon some examples which both illustrate and

    expand

    his point.

    The object

    of the

    examples

    is this:

    if

    someone

    who

    is strong

    wishes

    to be

    strong,

    or

    if

    someone

    who is

    healthy

    wishes to

    be healthy,

    what he

    really

    wishes

    is to

    continue

    to be strong

    or

    healthy

    in

    the

    future,

    something

    which

    he at present lacks.6

    But

    in the course

    of

    these

    examples,

    a

    new

    word

    is

    introduced

    to

    express

    that

    element

    of

    desire,

    namely

    ouXecaOL.

    It

    may

    seem

    at first

    that

    3ou'caoot

    and

    e7rLtieZvare used interchangeably in this passage, but if this were so,

    Socrates

    could be accused

    of

    ignoring

    the obvious difference

    that

    e7r&LOtLdv

    s

    primarily,

    if

    not

    exclusively,

    a

    passion,

    whereas

    PoUAeaOvL

    has

    the more

    intellectual

    connotation

    of

    wishing

    or

    willing.

    But

    he does

    not,

    I

    think,

    ignore

    this.

    Thus

    Socrates

    says

    at 200d,

    Con-

    sider,

    then,

    whether

    whenever

    you

    say

    that

    'I

    desire

    things

    now

    present,'

    you mean

    anything

    else

    than

    this, that

    'I

    wish to possess

    the things

    I now

    have

    in the

    future

    also. '

    This

    suggests

    that the

    desire

    for

    present

    possessions

    in the future

    somehow

    loses

    the

    pas-

    sionate

    force

    of a

    present

    desire

    (ChLOupdc)

    so

    that

    the more intellectual

    PoU'Xo,uim

    s

    appropriate.

    Let

    us

    call this

    introduction

    of

    Poi'Xo,oa?

    to

    refer

    to desire

    for

    future

    possession

    step

    four.

    Socrates

    then

    switches

    back

    to

    ?p&-v

    o draw

    his

    conclusion

    from

    the examples.

    But this

    is

    to love

    that

    which is

    not

    yet

    ready

    at

    hand

    for

    one,

    nor in

    one's possession,

    the

    possession

    and

    preservation

    of

    these things in future time. 7 Step five seems to establish that Epwg

    4

    Plato,

    Symposium,

    200a5.

    6 Ibid., 200a8.

    6

    Ibid.,

    200b8-200e.

    7

    Ibid.,

    200d8. ouxo5v ?o5Yr6

    y'&a-lv &xeEvou

    &p&v, ou'nwco

    ?tOL[LOV

    MUrT45

    &adv

    0o8e

    1XCL,

    6

    ?et

    t6V 17rCL'X

    Xp6vov

    'rac3rox

    tvot

    orCp

    cO6Lxcvac

    xodt

    nop6vro;

    34

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    4/15

    is also

    applicable

    to the

    possession

    of

    present

    blessings

    in the

    future

    - that

    locution

    to which

    the

    verb

    Poi')?eaO

    is appropriate.

    This

    man

    and

    anyone

    else

    who desires,

    says Socrates,

    desires

    what

    is not ready

    at hand

    nor

    present

    to him,

    and

    what he does

    not

    have, and

    what he

    is not himself

    and

    what

    he

    lacks,

    such are the

    kinds

    of things

    of which

    desire

    and love are. 8 Step

    six thus

    asserts

    that

    both

    Ep(o

    and ZatLOufL

    are

    of what

    one does not have,

    what

    one

    is not himself,

    and of

    what

    one

    lacks.

    Finally

    Socrates

    sums

    up

    the

    argument

    by

    establishing

    that

    vEpw4

    is first

    of

    something,

    and

    second,

    of

    something

    which one at

    present

    lacks (&Xo

    7L

    C'=tv

    6o

    Ep&g

    np&-ov

    ,ev

    'v

    mVov,

    ?7rsoo'Cro&v

    )v

    &oXv

    gv8eo ncpj

    ocUs&

    ).9

    The seventh and final step consists of droppingoff

    the interest

    in

    e'tLOUpa

    and

    concluding

    exclusively

    concerning

    `EpwG.

    Let

    us

    now

    examine the argument

    more closely to

    see

    what

    dis-

    tinctions

    develop.

    Step

    one establishes

    that

    'Epcjg

    desires,

    that is,

    that

    desiring

    is a

    possible predicate

    of

    Ep,og.

    It does

    not establish

    that

    desire

    is

    the

    only

    predicate

    of

    `Epws,

    nor,

    certainly,

    does it even

    hint

    that

    'Ep&o;

    nd

    EtLOvCu-.

    re identical,

    as

    Bury

    would have

    us

    believe.

    Step two increases the dubiousness of Bury's hypothesis when it

    adds that vEpco&

    oth

    desires and loves what it

    lacks. The

    only way

    this

    could

    be construed

    as

    implying

    that

    'Ep&o

    and

    eOur[Am

    re

    identical

    would

    be to

    interpret

    the presence

    of

    the

    conjunction

    here

    as a rather sophomoric

    redundancy

    on Plato's

    part.

    If

    vEpco=

    VXLOU.dm,

    hen

    the

    conjunction

    of the two

    is

    entirely

    unnecessary.

    A much more plausible

    explanation

    would be that by ascribing

    both

    loving

    and desiring

    as

    predicates

    of

    'Ep&g,

    having just

    ascribed

    desiring

    individually,

    Plato is

    indicating

    to us that there

    is

    at least

    some

    difference

    between

    them.

    What the

    difference

    is

    has as yet

    not

    even been

    hinted at.

    We see here

    only

    the

    suggestion

    that

    there is a

    difference.

    Step three

    is

    characterized

    by

    the

    fact

    that it

    tells us

    nothing

    directly

    about

    `Epco.

    It

    does,

    however,

    tell

    us

    something

    about

    enu&Aoc.10

    t tells us that

    desire

    desires,

    that it is self-predicative

    in

    S

    Ibid., 200el. xxl

    o5roq

    &pm

    al

    &XXoq

    iq

    6

    &kntOu(13v

    ro5

    ph

    &'rotLou

    xl

    SroV 0v?

    7rpOvrO;

    xoc

    6

    * lXCL

    XMt

    8

    IAj

    a-LV

    XT6q

    xma

    o5

    kvgt4 &aCrt,

    roLat

    r',r-m

    ta'rlv &v

    J

    &rLOuJAC

    -C

    xOd

    6

    Ip@

    &FTEV;

    9

    Ibid., 200e8.

    10

    Liddell and

    Scott, under

    &1=0u[&

    say

    that 'r

    IntOu?.ov

    ... equals

    &tOU[Eda.

    Although this may

    at times

    be

    debatable,

    it serves the

    point here; step

    three

    is

    about

    kMOu)imd,

    ot

    'Epw,.

    35

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    5/15

    the same

    way

    as

    'Epcoc.

    Epo~

    and

    sLOu&4o hus have this

    much in

    common:

    they

    both desire.

    'Epco,

    however loves

    (4p5)

    as

    well,

    i.e.,

    it too is

    self-predicative. One

    possible

    distinction

    between

    'Epco

    and

    6t0u,LOa

    now begins to emerge: they both desire, but only Epc?

    has

    been said to

    love. It

    may be that

    an0u[u(m

    an

    only

    desire,whereas

    'Epcog

    can

    both

    desire and love.

    Nor

    ought we

    to be

    surprised that

    such

    a

    difference arises.

    After all,

    VmOu,ul0

    s

    characterized by

    Plato

    in

    the

    Phaedrus as

    but the

    lowest

    faculty of

    the soul,

    as an unruly

    monster which

    must

    be

    constrained, sometimes

    violently

    constrained,

    by

    the

    higher

    faculties in order to

    prevent it

    from

    gaining

    complete

    mastery over

    the

    soul,1 whereas

    'Epco

    is

    portrayed in the

    same

    dialogue as divine

    madness,

    the source of

    inspiration

    to

    divine

    philosophy.112

    There

    must,

    then,

    be

    some other

    element

    in

    'Epco&

    n

    addition to its

    capacity

    to

    desire,

    which

    gives

    it the

    divine status

    which

    ehr&[da

    lacks.

    Looking

    forward to

    the ascent

    passage

    of

    the

    Symposium, the charioteer

    image

    of the

    Phaedrus,

    and even the

    cave

    analogy

    of the

    Republic,

    we could

    well

    suspect

    that

    it

    will

    be some

    element

    of

    rationality

    which will

    accomplish

    this

    enhancement

    of

    'Epco. When we think of the brute desire

    (EtLOu[da)

    of which 'Epco

    is

    capable,

    modified

    by

    a more rational

    element,

    our

    thought

    ought

    to turn to the

    possibilities offered

    by

    y6ac

    as a source

    of

    insight.

    Perhaps qtXEm

    s

    also involved in

    'Epo

    in a

    way

    which

    distinguishes

    'Epw

    from

    e.mOuiEa.

    o

    explore

    this

    possibility,

    we

    must turn to certain

    importantpassages

    in

    Plato's

    dialogue

    on

    (pLkax,

    he

    Lysis.

    The

    Lysis

    is a

    dialogue

    whose ostensible concern

    is

    the nature of a

    friend (pLX6;) r more broadly, of friendship

    (pLXcx).'8

    t might be

    pointed

    out that the

    very

    fact that Plato wrote one

    dialogue

    on

    friendship

    (ypXoc)

    nd

    two

    on

    'Epco

    indicates that he at least makes a

    distinction between these two

    terms,

    even if his commentators do

    not.

    What

    concerns

    us

    here, however,

    are

    certain

    illuminating

    statements

    on the

    possible

    relationship

    between

    'Epw4,

    9c0LX,

    and

    C7nLO04dc.

    Near

    the end of the

    dialogue,

    Socrates

    is

    pointing

    out that

    cXLai

    eed not

    be of what

    is

    absolutely

    evil or

    absolutely

    good,

    but

    possibly

    of

    something neither evil nor good. He says at one point, Is it possible

    for one

    desiring

    and

    loving

    not to befriend

    (p6elv)

    that which he

    desires

    and

    loves?

    (otov

    re

    oi9v

    earLv

    i7Ou&oUvrx'

    x

    ?L&pAv'a

    orouTOU

    I

    Plato, Phaedrus, 246ff.

    12

    Ibid., 244-246.

    18

    See D. N. Levin, op. cit. (n. 1), pages

    9-10 for a

    discussion

    of

    this.

    36

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    6/15

    0o

    eOtU.tL

    Xm,L

    P T

    (pLXBEZV;).14

    o

    which

    Lysis replies,

    It

    seems to

    me

    not.

    This

    sentence

    is most

    instructive,

    for

    it

    directly mentions

    and relates the

    three terms

    in

    question.

    It

    suggests

    that

    it

    is

    impossible

    for

    one

    desiring

    and

    loving

    (7rtLOouivat. xocL

    pxv-dr) not to

    befriend

    (FI?

    t9Xev)

    ts

    object.

    That

    is,

    if

    one

    both desires

    and

    loves

    (erLOUie

    xal

    kp-),

    he must

    also

    befriend

    (pLXd)

    as well.

    Now,

    we

    would

    hardly

    want

    to say

    that if one

    simply

    desired, he

    would

    also befriend.

    'ETLOu-

    tLCx,

    as the lower

    passion,

    would

    hardly

    deserve

    such

    a

    close

    association

    with the

    more rational

    yLX(c.

    The

    question

    as

    to

    whether one

    who

    loves

    (4p)

    also

    befriends

    (pXct)

    is

    more

    difficult,

    but

    probably con-

    tains

    the

    crux

    of our

    problem.

    I

    offer

    the

    following

    suggestion:

    it

    begins to look as though qLX6must be more closely associated with

    'Epw;

    than

    with

    C'mOulA.

    A

    hierarchy

    begins to

    emerge, with &rLOu-

    .daCt the

    bottom

    and

    (pLXLt

    the

    top,

    and

    these two

    terms

    mediated,

    as

    it

    were, by

    'Epwg,

    which

    contains

    elements of

    both.

    The criterion

    of

    this

    hierarchy

    clearly

    is

    involved

    with

    the

    degree of

    rationality

    implicit

    in the

    terms.

    'E=Oufao,

    the

    lower

    passion,

    contains

    virtually

    no

    rationality.

    In

    fact, it

    is a

    constant hindrance to

    reason,

    as

    we learn

    in the Phaedrus.'L Ep&s, as we learn from Diotima's revelation,

    contains

    a

    considerable element

    of

    reason

    or

    deliberative

    ability.

    It

    acts as

    the mediator between

    gods and men.16

    In

    its

    mythical pre-

    sentation

    as

    the son

    of Poros and

    Penia, it

    is described as

    ...

    plotting

    after

    beautiful

    things and

    good

    things, being

    manly

    and energetic

    and

    impetuous, a

    clever

    hunter,

    always weaving

    plots,

    desirous of

    thoughtfulness,

    inventive,

    a

    philosopher

    throughout

    its

    life.. .17

    Moreover,

    in

    the

    famous

    ascent

    passage ,'8

    we

    leam

    that

    as the

    degree

    of

    reason

    in

    'Epcs

    increases, whereby

    one

    turns his

    attention

    to

    increasingly higher

    objects

    of

    love,

    'Ep&q

    becomes

    transformed,

    in its

    highest

    manifestation, into

    p)LX,

    indeed the

    cpLXEm

    or

    aocptx,

    1

    Plato,

    Lysis, 221b. I have

    adopted

    to befriend

    for

    qlXtlv ,

    because

    it

    seemed

    the most

    plausible

    way to

    maintain

    the

    connection

    between

    qLxelv

    and

    TOA

    (friendship).

    However, it

    is in fact an

    inadequate

    translation, because it

    fails to

    bring

    out

    the

    subtlety

    of the distinction

    between

    (pOXcv,

    nd

    &p&.v

    n

    this

    sentence. The point is that

    9LxCLv

    has less

    17:LO[uLEa

    n it than does &p&v. ut to

    befriend is

    too weak.

    Both

    Ip&cv

    nd

    9LXclv

    should really

    be translated

    to love

    with the

    former understood to

    be

    somewhat

    stronger than the

    latter.

    15

    Plato, Phaedrus,

    247b,

    and

    elsewhere.

    16

    Plato, Symposium,

    202e.

    17

    Ibid., 203b-204, not

    to

    mention that

    in

    this

    description

    'Epcq

    is the veritable

    image

    of

    Socrates.

    Is

    Ibid.,

    210-212b.

    37

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    7/15

    or philosophy.

    00kXa, hen, is 'Epcosmodified by an increased

    degree

    of rationality.

    At the risk of

    being

    capricious

    we

    could say that the

    highest pursuit

    of man

    is not

    erosophy but philosophy

    because

    by the time man reacheshis highest condition, the erotic drive which

    started

    him on his way has

    been modified, but not sublimated,

    by

    an

    increased

    rationality,

    so that it becomes

    a

    pXtoc

    or wisdom. In

    fact, it is precisely

    this

    increased

    degree

    of

    rationality

    which has

    enabled

    man to settle his erotic drive on

    its

    most

    proper

    and

    highest

    object, wisdom itself.

    To

    hold such a view is

    not,

    of

    course, to

    maintain

    that

    there

    is

    no relation whatsoever between

    these terms. That even

    the two extremes,

    pL?E

    and

    e.LOUVd4x,

    are

    somewhat related

    is shown

    by a statement which Socrates

    makes shortly after the last quotation

    from

    the

    Lysis,

    at 221d. Desire

    is the

    cause

    of

    friendship,and that

    which desires

    is a friend

    to

    that which it desires, at the time

    when it

    desires.

    (4

    F

    tOuliEm

    rn

    ?tLcx,

    oclx(a,

    xal

    'o

    Z7rL0uLoiUvrp[LXov

    'oTv

    'O6'Z o6

    C7tlOu4LC

    xal'

    6o'-e

    6

    7LOt

    i

    u...).19

    Thus the

    desiring

    (so

    ZmLOt)ou)v)

    ecomes

    a friend to that which it desires

    in

    order o

    possess

    it.

    This

    illustrates that the two terms

    are

    related but different.

    Again,

    that

    Z'nu&.da

    is the cause of friendshipalso indicates that at least the

    extremes, cpL?,L

    and

    etLOuj.do

    re

    different,

    unless we wanted to hold

    the

    unlikely

    view that tLEot

    s a causa sui. This is

    reiterated

    in another

    way

    a few

    sentences

    later when Socrates argues that although we

    desire what

    we

    lack, nonetheless,

    Love and

    friendship

    and

    desire,

    as

    it seems happens

    to

    be

    of

    what

    belongs

    to it.

    (soiu

    o'Lxetou

    ,

    c

    gOtX?V,

    0

    T

    9p

    O

    aL

    Yn

    TqLX(

    XOCl

    )

    C7MOUpLLOCL

    UyXxVEL

    o?ia).20

    The fact

    that all three terms are mentioned again indicates that they are

    different, yet

    the content of the statement itself

    suggests

    another

    important

    similarity. Although

    all three

    are

    of what

    they

    do not

    have,

    their

    objects

    nonetheless

    are what

    belong

    to

    them,

    what is

    proper

    to them.21

    Let us

    now return to the order

    of

    argument

    in

    the

    Symposium.Step

    four

    contains the introduction

    of

    Po&'sXaeOt

    o

    apply

    to the desire for

    present possessions

    in the future. It is

    important

    to see that

    PoUAXaOt

    has at least this much in common with spavand

    &C70utOZV;

    it too is

    19

    Plato, Lysis,

    221d3.

    30

    Ibid., 221e3.

    31

    Let us remind ourselves

    again

    that to construe the ascription

    of the

    same

    predicate

    to these terms

    as an

    indication

    of their identity

    would be

    a wholly

    unsatisfactory

    procedure.

    38

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    8/15

    always of

    that which it lacks.22But 3Ou'XeAocthas the sense

    of deli-

    beration

    or

    reasoning

    for what

    one

    wishes,

    which sense

    &rntOuV.C

    acks.

    That is, the

    difference

    between

    the

    simple present

    desire

    (C'tMOUpit)

    and the assessment

    that the

    object

    is

    also desirable

    in the future

    (for

    which

    Poi'XeaOa

    is employed)

    is that the latter

    requires

    some element

    of

    deliberation

    as

    to the

    value

    (or

    at least

    desirability)

    of the

    object.

    At Republic

    438 aff., a passagewe

    shall

    consider

    later,

    Socrates satisfies

    Glaucon that an

    &ItLOuji(

    like

    thirst,

    makes

    no

    value

    judgment

    as

    to

    its

    object;

    it desires

    not

    good drink,

    but

    simply

    drink.

    Poueaott,

    on the other hand, suggests

    the deliberative

    or rational element

    whereby we

    assess

    the

    object

    of our desire as worth

    having in the

    future. Socrates' examples in the present passage are instructive in

    this

    regard.

    His examples of

    things which we

    wish for

    (3ouX6,eOoc)

    n

    the future are strength, health,

    and

    wealth.23

    Evidence for

    my

    view

    that these

    things require

    some deliberation

    before one seeks them

    (and

    are not simply objects

    of

    erLu&.do)

    s

    that these

    are

    precisely

    the three examples which Glaucon uses at

    Republic

    357c to convince

    Socrates of

    a third class

    of goods

    which

    require

    activities painful

    and unpleasant in themselves (exercise, being healed, working) but

    which are tolerated

    and consideredgood because

    of their

    good conse-

    quences.

    As step

    five

    indicates,

    this reasoned desire for present

    possessions

    in

    the future qualifies as

    `Epw4.

    This is

    to love that which

    is

    not

    present

    to one, and which he does not have... ('Ouxo5v oi5t6

    y'ea'sV

    ~xexsou

    9pV,

    8

    O57rcW

    roL[Lov

    c-rx

    IarV

    oi

    &

    ZXeL...),24

    This too suggests

    that the introduction of the

    deliberation

    involved in

    Po'X?rOoct

    ifts

    the status of the

    merely

    passionate

    &97c&4doo

    the level

    of

    Ep&g.

    Again

    we can

    argue

    that central to the distinction

    between

    es;tu41(a

    and 'Epcs

    is the presenceof

    rationality in

    'Epw;.

    Thus,

    concludes

    Socrates

    in

    step six,

    both desire

    and love are of

    what one does

    not have, of what one is not,

    and of what

    one

    lacks.

    This

    is consistent,

    because as we have seen,

    both Epco

    and

    e&irLQt

    desire,

    and one

    desires what

    one lacks. This conclusion,

    then,

    concerns

    only the fundamental similarity between Epto and Our?LEaocrates

    does not

    state

    explicitly

    the difference

    between

    these terms.

    That

    remains

    the enterpriseof the reader.

    In the

    summary of his

    discussion with

    Agathon, Socrates

    ceases

    22

    Plato,

    Symposium,

    200b.

    23

    Ibid.,

    200d.

    '4

    Ibid., 200d8.

    39

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    9/15

    mentioning

    both

    'Ep;

    and

    krOupia

    and concludes exclusively con-

    cerning

    Epw.

    This is because the

    stated topic of conversation s 'Epcoc

    not

    C'Ovudca.

    We have

    learned

    about

    &7rLOutLm

    oo in this discussion,

    as well as about

    cpOEm,

    but the explicit purpose in the context of

    the Symposium

    has been to determine

    certain

    things about

    Epco;.

    We have learned

    that Epoj is always directed towards

    an object,

    and that its object

    is

    always

    something that it

    lacks.

    In the context of these remarks

    about the

    nature of

    'Epwq

    in the

    Symposium,

    we

    have seen the

    necessity

    of

    making

    a

    more complex

    distinction between

    three related

    but different terms:

    C7LOu['to,

    'Epo;,

    and

    cptXM.

    et

    me try to sum up in a coherent fashion

    the distinctions

    which have so far emerged.

    'EmtOu[da

    e know to be the lowest

    faculty of the

    soul, the brute desire

    to possess what one lacks.

    'Epco;

    also desires,but unlike

    mLOutita,

    which only

    desires,

    Epwo

    both

    desires

    and loves.

    The difference

    between

    'Epo

    and

    ?tLOu,u(a,

    hen

    must

    lie in this

    and loves.

    I

    have suggested that the qualitative

    differencebetween

    'Epco&

    nd

    'r=Ouda(

    ies

    in the

    presence

    of

    rationality

    in

    'Epwg.

    In

    its purest form,

    the modification

    of the

    desire

    for

    possession

    by rationality or contemplation is y&X6.The aspect of Epwsand

    ctoc

    is thus a rational or contemplative aspect

    which is

    usually

    accompaniedby desire.

    I

    propose now

    to cite several passages both

    in

    the Symposium

    and

    in

    other dialogues,

    in

    which

    the thesis that there

    is

    a

    distinction

    between

    L7tOUi.to,

    Ep&gand

    ytEa,

    and

    that the distinction hinges

    on

    the presence

    and degree

    of

    reason

    in

    each,

    is

    borne

    out.

    At

    the

    same time I shall begin to suggest certain philosophic consequences

    whichfollow therefrom.

    To take the

    ascent passage

    of the Symposium

    first;

    in that

    pas-

    sage

    we

    are

    presented

    with the

    erotic ascent

    of a

    lover and

    potential

    philosopher from

    the love of one beautiful body,

    through the

    love of

    all

    physical beauty, through the

    love

    of increasingly higher objects,

    to

    the

    love of

    the beauty of knowledge,

    and

    finally

    to the

    love

    of

    Beauty itself.

    This ascent is endlessly

    rich with philosophicpossibilities,

    but we must confine ourselves here to an examination of what it can

    tell us

    about

    the distinction

    between

    'Epco;,

    mOu,i(m

    and

    ypLX(m.

    The first thing to notice is the first

    step: It is necessary

    says Diotima,

    for

    one

    rightly

    pursuing this business to begin

    when

    he is

    young by

    pursuing beautiful bodies, and first

    if he is rightly

    led by

    his

    leader,

    he will

    love one body and in it

    he

    will

    beget beautiful

    speeches. 25

    25

    Ibid., 210a4.

    40

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    10/15

    We see here that

    although

    Plato

    begins

    the erotic ascent to

    philosophy

    on

    a much more

    concrete level

    than

    many

    philosophers

    would

    be

    willing

    to grant, he has still not

    begun

    at the

    most concrete

    level.

    For Plato has Diotima

    begin

    this

    ascent at what

    is

    already

    a

    fairly

    advanced

    stage

    of

    development;

    the

    young person

    in

    question has

    already

    discerned the

    beauty

    of the

    physical

    body,

    and

    picked

    out

    that

    quality

    as

    worthy

    of love. The

    higher

    level of this first

    step

    is

    also

    indicated by

    the manner of

    generation

    which

    results;

    the

    lover

    will

    generate not human

    children,

    or even sexual

    gratification,

    but

    beauti-

    ful

    speeches

    (?o6you

    ocXoi))

    n the

    soul of

    the

    beloved. A

    prior

    stage

    of

    development, then, would have

    been

    an

    undiscerning

    or

    indiscri-

    minate desire for the possession of the physical body, a desire whose

    generative

    issue

    would have been sexual

    gratification,

    or

    at best

    (if

    the affair

    were

    heterosexual)

    human

    children.

    But what else

    would

    that

    desire be but

    &7rLOuutO

    This

    ascent

    is an

    ascent of

    Ep&o,

    and

    therefore does

    not

    begin with

    the

    absolutely

    lowest

    level,

    which

    would

    be

    &7rOu,(ac.

    A

    complete

    ascent would

    necessitate a

    beginning with

    pure

    i'mOultm,

    or

    desire for

    the possession of a

    physical

    body, that

    is,

    for sexual intercourse.Plato has given us that beginning in an earlier

    ascent

    just

    prior

    to

    the

    present

    one,

    which was

    stated

    in

    terms of

    the desire

    (ZhrOudoc)

    or

    generation.26

    There,

    the

    ascent

    began

    with the

    lOUpd

    for

    procreation,which was

    characteristic even of

    beasts,

    and

    ascended to such

    higher

    procreations as

    the

    works of

    Homer and

    Hesiod, and

    the

    laws of

    Solon

    and

    Lycurgos. If we

    were

    now to

    juxta-

    pose

    these two

    ascents,

    we would

    see

    that

    the first

    ascent

    constituted

    the

    absolute

    beginning,

    whereas

    the

    beginning

    of

    the second

    ascent,

    the

    one now in

    question,

    already

    represents a

    certain

    stage of

    deve-

    lopment. And

    what

    precisely is that

    stage? It is

    the

    stage

    of dis-

    criminatingor

    reasoningcapacity

    which our

    earlier

    analysis suggested

    differentiates

    Epoc

    from

    Cr&LOdcu.

    It

    is

    also worth

    noting that

    the

    highest

    stage

    of the

    earlier ascent

    (of desire for

    procreation),

    aws

    and

    politics

    (exemplified

    by Solon

    and

    Lycurgus)

    27

    is

    but a

    middle

    level in

    the more

    famous ascent of the

    love of beauty.28 Whatever the deeper reasons for this, it reveals

    that

    m7rOu[Aoc

    nd

    'Ep&4

    overlap, but

    'Ep(o

    has

    higher

    manifestations

    than

    does

    'LmOu[da,

    n

    particular

    the

    two

    highest

    steps

    on the philo-

    sophic

    ascent, love of

    knowledge

    (popOL,a6E)

    nd love

    of

    Beauty

    26

    Ibid.,

    207-210.

    27

    Ibid.,

    209d.

    28

    Ibid.,

    210c.

    41

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    11/15

    Itself

    (ypXoaopc).

    This was indicated in our

    analysis

    by the fact that

    'Ep&o

    and

    C'=Ouda

    both desire

    -

    this is where they overlap

    -

    yet the

    reasoning ability of which Epwg

    s capable makes it higher.

    A look at the transitions in the erotic ascent to Beauty Itself

    again shows the involvement of

    reason and

    Epcoq.

    or the redirection

    of

    one's Ep&o rom one step

    to another, for instance from the love

    of one beautiful body

    to

    the

    love of all physical beauty, is accomplish-

    ed

    when one realizes

    (VVonamV

    O)29

    that the beauty of all physical

    things

    is

    related.

    Thus the ascent of

    Epcog,he redirection of one's

    'Epwg

    on

    increasingly worthy

    objects, is possible because of the

    in-

    creased presenceof reason

    in

    Ep&o.

    In the last two steps of the ascent, the love of all knowledge, and

    the love of Beauty Itself, one's

    Ep&;has become so imbued

    with

    reason that

    it is

    more properly

    called

    (cpLoc,

    ndeed, the

    pL?Wa

    for

    aop6x.

    For

    in the

    next

    to the last step, the love of the beauty of

    all

    knowledge

    (ZhUaTn[),

    the aspirant

    is

    partaking

    in

    unencumbered

    philosophy

    (v

    pXoaoptoc

    Op06v),30

    and of

    course,

    in

    the

    last

    step,

    the glimpse

    of

    Beauty Itself,

    one is at

    the level of

    philosophy

    too.

    This also supports the results of our earlier analysis; the difference

    between Ep&g nd cpcao

    s

    one

    of

    degree.

    And

    the

    degree

    in

    question

    is

    the degree of reason

    which

    is

    present

    in

    one's Ep&g.

    Thus the

    ''ascent

    passage

    is

    entirely

    consistent

    with

    the results

    of our

    earlier

    analysis, both

    in

    regard

    to the

    order

    of

    the

    hierarchy

    (efLQu[dc-'Epwq-

    ypaLXL)

    and

    in

    regard

    to

    the

    principle

    of

    differentiation:

    the

    presence

    and

    degree

    of reason.

    My thesis also finds ample support in Plato's other great dialogue

    on

    'Ep&o,

    the

    Phaedrus. To

    take

    the

    negative way first;

    in the

    speech of Lysias, and

    more

    importantly,

    in the

    first

    speech

    of

    Socrates

    for

    which

    he

    must later

    offer

    a

    recantation,

    Ep(o4

    s

    indeed

    identified

    with

    ehnNu,i..

    He

    defines

    Epcog

    n this

    speech

    as irrationaldesire

    ('

    &veu

    Xoyou ebtLOtdo)31

    which,

    far from

    inspiring

    one

    to

    philosophy

    as

    the Symposium suggests,

    rather

    prevents

    both

    the

    lover

    and

    his

    beloved

    from

    pursuing

    divine

    philosophy. 32

    t

    is clear

    throughout

    these first two speeches that Epc is interpreted, and censured, as

    irrational

    and harmful

    sexual

    lust,

    or

    ehr&tLta.

    his is

    why

    both

    speeches

    advocate

    that

    one

    avoid

    relationships

    with

    lovers.

    Yet

    Socrates

    29

    Ibid.,

    210b.

    20

    Ibid.,

    210d6.

    al

    Plato,

    Phaedrus,

    238b7.

    32

    Ibid.,

    239b.

    42

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    12/15

    insists

    that he

    make a recantation for

    this

    speech because it was a

    sin

    against

    'Epw, 33

    the sort

    of thing one would

    expect

    to hear

    from

    sailors

    who

    had never

    experienced

    any higher

    love.34

    Clearly then,

    this

    interpretation

    of

    Epwg

    s to be

    rejected.

    The

    more positive

    statement of

    the nature and function

    of the

    soul's

    'Epwq

    in

    Socrates'

    second speech offers even

    stronger

    support

    for

    my

    thesis. There the famous

    charioteer

    image

    is

    presented; the

    soul

    is

    likened

    to a team

    of

    horses and

    a

    charioteer.

    The black,

    ugly,

    unmanageable

    horse,

    it is

    usually agreed,

    represents

    desire, or

    entOu[LEo.

    he handsome white

    horse,

    more obedient to the

    orders

    of

    the

    charioteer,

    represents spirit

    (Ouli6q).

    The

    distinction

    between

    'Epw; and kn&Ou[Aa.s clear from the outset;

    ?shOur.ta,

    represented by

    the black

    horse,

    is the lowest and

    most

    unruly faculty

    of

    the soul, a

    constant danger

    to its higher functions.

    'Epcoq,

    however,

    is divine

    madness

    which

    pervades

    the whole

    soul.

    Indeed,

    one

    crucialdifference

    between

    'Epw~ and

    inOuti?M

    is

    the relation of each to

    the

    charioteer,

    reason.

    'En&sL'o.c,he black

    horse, resists and

    disobeys the

    charioteer

    whenever possible.35 Ep&o,

    on the

    contrary,

    finds its fulfillment (in

    philosophy) only when the charioteer is in proper command. Per-

    vading

    the

    whole

    soul,

    Epwq

    ontains

    in

    its nature

    desire,

    spirit,

    and

    reason. But its fulfillment

    requires

    that

    the

    reason

    which is

    part

    of

    its

    nature exhibit its

    presence

    and control

    over its

    ?tnLOU[.da

    6

    This

    should

    be sufficient to

    show that

    it is

    only when

    reason

    is

    sufficiently

    present and

    active

    in

    'Ep&q

    hat

    'Epw;

    can

    achieve its

    highest mani-

    festation,

    in

    philosophy.

    Remembering

    that at this

    highest mani-

    festation, Epcos

    s

    indeed

    a

    cpLXEa,

    e can

    see that this

    passage

    alsois

    consistent

    with the

    distinction,

    however

    slight,

    between

    Epwq

    and

    tEoc,

    a distinction of

    which Plato indicates he is

    aware at

    Phaedrus

    255e,

    where the

    young beloved mistakes

    his

    feelings

    of

    Ep&g or

    cpLXt.

    Thus all the distinctions which

    we found

    present

    in

    the

    Sym-

    posium

    are also

    present

    in

    the

    Phaedrus;

    'Epco, kbrOupdo,

    and

    cpLtX

    are

    all

    differentiated,

    and the

    principle

    of

    differentiation is

    the pre-

    sence and

    degree

    of reason.

    I wish now to turn briefly to the Republicwhere support is also

    present for my view. It

    will

    be

    remembered that one

    stage

    in

    my

    88

    Ibid.,

    242e4.

    84

    Ibid.,

    243c5.

    85

    Ibid.,

    253e,

    254a,

    254c,

    el.

    al.

    Il

    This

    is a constant theme

    throughout

    the

    speech.

    See

    especially

    the remark

    of

    of

    Socrates at 256a8.

    43

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    13/15

    argument

    from

    the Symposium

    concerned

    the

    introduction

    of the

    term

    PoueafxL

    which

    was to

    be

    distinguished

    from ?UL#OuLCZV

    nd

    which pointed

    the

    way to

    4p&v.37

    The

    distinction between

    ?7rVrLOUZV

    and

    poUAeaOaL

    s indicated

    in the Republicat

    437b-c,

    where Socrates

    is

    establishing

    the

    tripartite

    division

    of the soul.

    He

    wants

    to show

    that

    desire

    (e7tOu[L(a)

    s

    one of these

    parts,

    and in so doing says,

    What then,

    said

    I,

    of thirst and

    hunger

    and the desires generally,

    and

    again

    (my italics)

    willing

    and wishing... (-r[ou'v;

    jv

    'y6')c

    aLt4v

    xalJ~

    t?lVmV XMt

    6X,( e'7r&

    OUtL'M

    XOcdt5

    'r O

    XeLv

    xaL

    'rs

    po,a...)

    My

    point here is

    that

    by distinguishing

    the

    desires

    (k

    e'7vOu[Eoc;)

    from

    wishing ('r6

    PouieaOoc),

    indeed emphasizing

    the distinction

    by

    the use of and again (xot oa5),we see that that distinction is held

    consistently

    in this

    dialogue

    too.38

    Again,

    this

    by

    way

    of

    support

    for

    the difference

    between 'Epw

    and

    ehr&u,uL,

    Socrates at

    438a

    is satis-

    fying

    Glaucon

    that

    desire, qua

    desire,

    is only

    of its object,

    with

    no

    further qualifications.

    He

    warnsGlaucon,

    'Let no one then,'

    said

    I,

    'disconcert

    us when off our guard

    with

    the

    objection

    that everybody

    desires not drink but good drink

    (4g

    oC8clg

    noTro5

    ntLOu Zt

    X

    Xp ro'roo3)nd not food but good food because all men desire good

    (7r6iv'T?

    yip

    &pa

    -r&v

    &yaxO&v

    n&rOto5atv)

    nd so if thirst is

    desire

    it would

    be

    of good

    drink

    or

    of

    good

    whatsoever it

    is;

    and so similarly

    of other desires. '

    8

    Since

    hrrLu.Ltca

    s not to

    be understood

    as discriminating

    between

    objects

    as to their goodness,

    it

    must surely

    be differentiated

    from

    'Epus

    which

    in

    the Symposium

    is

    defined

    as of the eternal

    possession

    of the

    good. 40

    Finally, to point to one of the so-called earlierdialogues, the

    Charmides

    offers

    appropriate

    support

    for some of

    the distinctions

    I

    have drawn.4

    At

    Charmides

    167e,

    Socrates

    is concerned

    to

    call

    into

    question

    the

    possibility

    that wisdom

    should

    have

    no

    subject

    matter

    of

    its own,

    but

    rather be the science of sciences.

    To

    repudiate

    this,

    87

    Above, pp. 38-39.

    38

    On

    the other

    hand,

    see

    Republic

    439a9,

    where Socrates

    uses

    Po6Xvrau

    s

    virtual-

    ly synonymous

    with

    kn&Outet,

    here

    the subtle distinction

    between

    them is not

    important.

    39

    Translation

    is that of

    Paul

    Shorey.

    See also

    439a-b.

    40

    Plato, Symposium,

    206a. Notice

    that

    at Symposium

    205a,

    Diotima, by way

    of correcting

    Aristophanes,

    asserts that people

    will even

    cut off a

    part

    of

    them-

    selves if they think

    it will bring them good.

    41

    I

    wish to thank David

    Gallop

    for

    pointing

    out

    these

    passages

    to me.

    The

    interpretation

    of them

    presented

    here is of course

    my

    own responsibility.

    44

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    14/15

    he cites

    several

    parallel

    cases

    where,

    he suspects,

    the implausibility

    wil

    be obvious.

    Three of these examples

    are especially relevant

    to

    the present problem,

    for they again

    indicate a consistent

    maintenance

    of the

    relevant distinctions

    on Plato's

    part.

    Socrates

    says

    at 167e,

    Could there

    be

    any

    desire

    (7rt0upAm)

    hich

    is not the desire of

    any

    pleasure,

    but of itself

    and of all other desires? Certainly

    not. Or

    can

    you imagine

    a

    wish

    (Po0X7atq)

    which wishes

    (Ao6XrcxL)

    for no

    good,

    but

    only

    for itself

    and all

    other

    wishes? I should

    answer no. Or would

    you

    say that

    there is a love

    (fpcom)

    which

    is not the

    love of

    beauty,

    but

    of

    itself

    and

    of other loves?

    I should

    not. '2

    We

    notice first that

    the three terms

    are

    distinguished, supporting

    the thesis

    of this

    paper.

    But the

    way

    in which

    they

    are

    distinguished,

    namely, according to their objects, is also significant. The object of

    &vutAa

    s

    pleasure.

    This differentiates it

    from

    'Epcos

    both

    in

    this

    dialogue

    and

    in

    Socrates' speech

    in the

    Symposiun.

    Significantly

    enough,

    the

    object

    of

    Epcos

    s the Charmides

    s

    beauty (sorxocX6v)

    whereas that of

    Pou'-aL

    is

    the good

    (ro6

    &yaO6v).

    n the Symposium

    both

    Agathon

    and the

    young

    Socrates

    begin

    with the view that

    'Epco;'

    object

    is the beautiful but

    are

    corrected

    by

    Diotima,

    who shows

    that

    'Ept' true object is the good. Perhapswe could say that this transi-

    tion

    was

    prefigured

    by the transition

    which

    I

    treated

    earlier from

    ?7mOlutoA

    o

    'Epco;,

    where these two terms

    were

    mediated,

    as

    it were,

    by ,Bou')CGaO,

    hose object,

    we learn now

    in the Charmides,

    s the good.

    If

    so,

    we see again the remarkable

    consistency

    with

    which Plato used

    these

    important terms.

    Still

    further,

    we see

    again

    that one

    consequence of the

    different

    objects

    of

    Oupidcx

    nd

    Pou'i)Xa

    (pleasure

    and

    the good) is that

    PoUA-mLq

    equires, over and above the simple desire for the object,

    the

    deliberative ability wherewith to

    assess that

    its object

    is good,

    once

    again supporting

    the distinction

    drawn earlier between

    these

    two terms.46

    Such

    is

    the evidence

    I

    wish to put forward

    for

    the

    hierarchical

    distinction

    between

    brLOu,da,

    Epus, and

    cpara

    based on the

    degree

    and presence

    of

    reason. Some

    of the consequences

    of this view

    for the

    4I

    Translation is

    that of Jowett.

    48

    Plato,

    Symposium, 205-206a.

    44 Above, pp.

    38-39.

    6

    That the object

    of

    'Epws

    also involves this

    deliberative ability

    is

    supported

    by

    a

    general

    consideration of

    Socrates's speech

    in

    the Symposium,

    but

    especially

    by the

    correction

    mentioned above, that

    'Epcw

    most proper object

    is

    really the

    good.

    45

  • 8/9/2019 ῎Ερως, ᾿Επιθυμία, and Φιλία in Plato (Drew A. Hyland)

    15/15

    Symposium, and in particular for

    the important ascent passage ,

    I

    have already noted.

    I

    would like to conclude by suggesting a far

    more pervasive consequence. If

    Plato is indeed suggesting, as I

    maintain, that reason is not

    merely occasionally interrelated with,

    but indeed

    part

    of the

    very

    nature of

    Epcoq,

    s

    opposed

    to

    desire,

    then he forces us to reconsiderthe

    notion, popular

    in

    his day as it is

    today, that love

    is

    necessarily and

    unambiguously

    in

    the realm of

    the irrational.

    By

    extension he

    forces

    us to reconsider

    such clear-

    cut distinctions in Greek thought as

    Nietzsche popularized between

    the Dionysian

    and

    the Apollonian.

    Finally by lifting 'Ep&o

    from

    the

    realm of irrational feeling, Plato avoids the rather bizarre conse-

    quence that philosophy, which is after all a species of love, would,

    while standing

    as the

    champion

    of

    rationality,

    have its base

    in

    the

    utterly, exclusively,

    irrational.

    As

    Nietzsche

    himself

    said in Thus

    Spoke

    Zarathustra:

    True,

    we

    love

    life,

    not

    because we are

    used

    to

    living but because

    we

    are

    used to

    loving.

    There

    is

    always

    some madness

    in love.

    But

    there is

    always

    some

    reason n

    madness. 46

    46 Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, translated by Walter Kaufmann in The

    Portable

    Nietzsche,

    Viking Press,

    New York, page

    153.

    Trinty

    College,Hartford,

    Connecticut.